Edge: THE NATURE OF NORMAL HUMAN VARIETY A Talk with Armand Leroi


Of course, there will be people who object. There will be people who will say that this is a revival of racial science. Perhaps so. I would argue, however, that even if this is a revival of racial science, we should engage in it for it does not follow that it is a revival of racist science. Indeed, I would argue, that it is just the opposite.

THE NATURE OF NORMAL HUMAN VARIETY [3.15.05]
A Talk with Armand Leroi


THE REALITY CLUB: James J. ODonnell, Andrew Brown, Tim D. White, Alun Anderson, Nicholas Humphrey respond to Armand Leroi
Introduction

In the early '90s, I was visiting Cambridge and went out to dinner with the late Stephen Jay Gould. During a long evening of conversation we talked about his ideas concerning race, racial racial differences, racial equality, including his well-known writings on the use and misuse of IQ tests and other such measures. I came away from the conversation with the distinct sense that he believed there were some things better left unsaid, some areas of investigation that were out of bounds if he wanted to have a just society. Nothing strange here. His views were, and still are, consistent with the daily fare of the editorial pages of many of our important newspapers and magazines.

Armand Leroi, a biologist at Imperial College, feels differently. He loves what he calls "the problem of normal human variety".

"Almost uniquely among modern scientific problems, he says, "it is a problem that we can apprehend as we walk down the street. We live in an age now where the deepest scientific problems are buried away from our immediate perception. They concern the origin of the universe. They concern the relationships of subatomic particles. They concern the nature and structure of the human genome. Nobody can see these things without large bits of expensive equipment. But when I consider the problem of human variety I feel as Aristotle must have felt when he first walked down to the shore at Lesvos for the first time. The world is new again. What is more, it is a problem that we can now solve, a question we can now answer. And I think we should.

"Of course, there will be people who object. There will be people who will say that this is a revival of racial science". Leroi argues that "there will always be people who wish to construct socially unjust theories about racial differences. And though it is true that science can be bent to evil ends, it is more often the case that injustice creeps in through the cracks of our ignorance than anything else. It is to finally close off those cracks that we should be studying the genetic basis of human variety."

—JB

ARMAND LEROI is a Reader in Evolutionary Developmental Biology at Imperial College, London. He is the author of Mutants: On Genetic Variety and the Human Body, winner of The Guardian First Book Award, 2004.


THE NATURE OF NORMAL HUMAN VARIETY

(ARMAND LEROI:) The question that interests me, as it does so many other people, is how to go about making a human being. It's a very difficult problem. Roughly what it boils down to is this: We have 30,000 genes or so. It's often said that the genome is something in the nature of a book. It has words, a grammar, a syntax, and of course those words have meaning. The only problem is that we don't know actually what that meaning is. So the question is, how do we decipher that? And turning that question around, looking at it from the point of the human body, what do those genes mean to the construction of the human body?

Of course, I myself don't actually work on humans. They're just too inconvenient. I work on worms. This worm is Caenorhabditis elegans, for which Brenner, Sulston, and Horvitz just won the Nobel Prize. And the reason why I and a thousand other scientists work on this worm is that, for all of their marvelous properties, it's easy to keep thousands of them in petri dishes, and it's very easy to find mutants. And that's the critical thing. We find mutants that interrupt particular genes, and that tells us what those genes do and what they mean to the body of a worm.

Developmental biologists have been doing this for a long time—once a field has its Nobel, you can be sure it's reasonably mature. What people haven't really done, however, is to do this for the human body. The reason is obvious: you just can't go out and generate mutants in humans. For humans you've got to go out and find those mutants. But they're out there. There are thousands upon thousands of mutants out there—no, more, millions—no, actually billions. This is because we are all mutants. That's one thing you don't expect but which happens to be statistically true. Each of us carries mutations that interrupt particular genes. So if you can just find who is a mutant for a particular gene, and examine what they look like, you can actually then work out what those genes do.

This raises a question: what exactly is a mutant? Worm biologists and fly biologists—geneticists generally, working on model organisms—use the word "mutant" in a very particular way. In worms and flies there is an arbitrarily defined strain which we call the "wild type". But in humans there is no arbitrary wild type. So can you, in fact, speak of mutant humans?

You can, but the definition of what is a mutant in humans is necessarily more roundabout. This is because we have such an extraordinary amount of natural variation in our species. If you go around the world you see tall people, short people, red-haired people, brown-haired people, people with curly hair, people with no hair, and so on. Given all this variation, what exactly, and who exactly, is a mutant? It's an important question, because to say something is a mutant is in fact to make an invidious distinction. This is to say something is not just different but actually abnormal in some fashion. Yet despite the fact that there is so much variation in our species, it is actually possible to speak in a coherent way of mutations and of mutants in humans.

Roughly, the reason you can do this is as follows: If you look at the coding sequence, more precisely, the protein sequence produced by any given gene, it's the case that for most genes nearly everybody has the same version. True, there are some genes that are polymorphic — variable — and these are genes that give us all our natural diversity. But they actually constitute a very small fraction of the genome. Most people have the same functional version of a gene. Given that fact, you can define a mutant as somebody who has a rare variant of a gene, moreover, a variant that harms him in some fashion. And if you look at it that way, it's clear that we all carry rare variants that do us harm in some way, and that we are in fact all mutants.

We can even put some numbers on this. One of the really surprising results in recent years, which comes from the comparison of the genomes of different species, is that every newborn child carries three novel deleterious mutations, that is, mutations that its parents didn't have. Not only that, but each child inherits at least some of the mutations that its parents have as well. It's estimated then — and of course this is just an estimate — that every newly conceived person has something like 300 mutations that affect its health for the worse in some fashion.

Of course, that number doesn't tell us a whole lot. We not only need to know about the number of mutations that we have, but also the distribution of their effects. This is because some mutations have very severe effects. They are the mutations that cause the big known inherited diseases — and about 10,000 such diseases have been identified so far. But there must be many, many more mutations that do us harm, but only subtly so. These are the mutations that give us weak eyes, bad backs and the like. These are mutations that we know very little about but that statistically speaking must be there. It's actually in these mutations that a lot of human health lies—or rather the absence of human health lies. At least it does once you have gotten rid of the contagious diseases.

When I speak of mutations that do somebody harm what I really mean is not so much that they just affect physiological health; what I really mean is they affect the Darwinian fitness, the probability that they will reproduce. It's an evolutionary definition. It's the kind of definition that can encompass an enormous range of impairments, and the kinds of impairments that you see that are caused by mutations are at times of a degree and of a form that you really just cannot conceive of.

If you go to teratology museums—literally "monstrosity museums"—in places such as Amsterdam and Philadelphia, you can see rows of babies in bottles. These infants, usually stillborn, are deformed in ways that are truly hideous, that really represent the kinds of monstrosities that you might expect from Greek myth. I mean this quite literally. They include children born with a single eye in the middle of their forehead, and who look exactly like the monsters of Greek myth—Polyphemus in The Odyssey, for example. Indeed, it's sometimes suggested that the monsters of Greek myth were inspired by deformed children, and this seems to be a fairly remarkable correspondence, at least with some of them.

These infants, when you see them, are truly horrific. But very quickly, after you look at them, a sort of intellectual fascination takes over because it's clear that these children tell us something very deep about how the human body is built. Take, for instance, these children with a single eye in the middle of their foreheads. The syndrome is called, appropriately, Cyclopia. Cyclopia is caused by a deficiency in a gene called Sonic hedgehog. Sonic hedgehog is named after a fruit fly gene which when mutated causes bristles to sprout all over the fruit fly larva, hence "hedgehog". When the gene was found in mammals, some wit called it Sonic hedgehog after the video game character. If you get rid of this gene, bad things happen. You lose your arms beneath the elbow and legs beneath the knee. The face collapses in on itself, such that you get a single eye in the middle of the forehead and the rest of the face collapses into a long, trunk-like proboscis. The forebrain, which is normally divided such that we have a left and a right brain—the left and right cerebral hemispheres—is fused into a single unitary structure. Indeed the technical name for this syndrome is called Holoprosencephaly.

Now all this is very horrible, and actually that's just an initial list of things that can go wrong in infants that have no Sonic hedgehog. But what's really interesting about it is that by looking at infants of this sort you can reverse-engineer and ask what Sonic hedgehog does in the embryo. Instantly it tells you that one of the things that Sonic hedgehog does is to keep our eyes apart because if you don't have the gene the face collapses. It also separates the left and and right sides of our brains. And it's needed for the formation of our arms and legs. In fact, it is one of the most ubiquitous and powerful molecules in the making of our bodies.

And other, more subtle mutations, tell more about it. For example, just as having too little Sonic hedgehog causes the face to collapse in upon itself, having too much causes it to expand. I was recently in San Francisco, in Jill Helms's lab at the University of California, San Francisco, where she's got a jar containing the head of a pig. Or is it two pigs? It's just not clear since the jar contains a pig with two faces, two snouts, two tongues, two throats, and three eyes. It's not a Siamese twin pig; it's just a pig with two faces. Chickens and pigs with two faces crop up periodically, as indeed do humans with two faces, or nearly two faces. There's a syndrome in which you have eyes that are very widely spaced from each other, and in which the nose becomes duplicated. You have two noses side by side in two varying degrees of development.

The gene for this syndrome has recently been cloned, and guess what? It turns out to be the gene that controls Sonic hedgehog, and that, in fact, switches it off. People with the syndrome have too much Sonic hedgehog just as infants with Cyclopia have too little. So by looking at a range of these kinds of syndromes you can put together a very complete picture of how a gene like Sonic hedgehog controls one particular feature of us, the width of our faces. It's a very mundane thing that you'd hardly think about, but that seems to be controlled by this genetic system.

There are many other disorders that equally informative. The star at the Mütter Museum at the College of Physicians of Philadelphia is Harry Eastlack, a man who had a disease called Fibrodysplasia Ossificans Progressiva. It's a disorder in which supernumerary bones form. The Mütter Museum has his skeleton, which he donated at the time of his death when he was in his forties. The skeleton is essentially not one man's skeleton—it is, as it were, one skeleton encased in another. What happens in this disorder is that wherever you get a bruise or a wound, instead of normal cells moving in to regenerate the skin and the flesh and heal the wound, bone forms. So every bruise turns to bone. The kids are born relatively normal, but as they go through life bone accretes all over them such that they can no longer move. They become rigid, locked into place. You can cut it away, of course, but as soon as you make an incision, and that incision heals, more bone forms. So it's a vicious circle. We don't know which gene is mutated in this syndrome. But it's almost certainly got something to do with bone morphogenetic protein, a protein that is, as the name suggests, normally involved in making bone in infants. It's just that in most of us this gene switches off. In these people this protein keeps on being produced throughout life, especially when there's a wound. It's another marvelous instance of how a given mutation can tell us something important about how bones are formed. FOP is a very rare disorder, and the reason why the gene hasn't been cloned is because to identify genes, to clone genes, you need to have big pedigrees. At least it helps. But these people just never have children.

People sometimes ask what developmental biology is good for. We can identify genes that are responsible for making this or that part of the human body. But in humans, of course, there's a very pressing question: namely, how can you fix the deleterious consequences of these mutations? It's one thing to go into a clinical genetics ward, a pediatric ward, and study kids who are seriously deformed, and say, "This is just terribly interesting. Your son is highly informative about the function of the Jagged-2 gene." — but that's not a great deal of comfort to the parents who actually have to deal with raising children who are variously deformed and may die or, at the very least, have to undergo a great deal of surgery. That, of course, is the problem. The molecular biology is beautiful, but when it actually comes to curing people, you just have surgery — which is little more than a rather sophisticated form of butchery.

The great promise, of course—and it's been a promise for years now and will remain so for some time—is that by learning about what genes do and how organs and tissues are constructed we can reconstruct them as we wish. By working out the program we can take cells, put them in a test-tube, and rebuild tissues. You don't have cartilage in your larynx? We can build it for your child, and we can fix it. You don't have a breast? We can rebuild that, too. And so on. This is a whole new area called tissue engineering. There are big institutes devoted to it now, where engineers, materials scientists, and molecular biologists are all working together. So far, it must be said, it's more institution building and propaganda than real results, but it'll happen. That is when the justification for this whole science will ultimately come.

There's no doubt that when you see some of these children who are so terribly deformed, it's very difficult. It's shocking, it's heartbreaking, and if you spend any time with them, whether they're alive in pediatric wards, or whether they're just babies in bottles, it takes a real psychological toll. I certainly don't ever get completely hardened to it. But what is also true is that intellectual fascination of seeing what has gone wrong in these unusual bodies takes over. This is especially the case when your eye is attuned to perceiving the differences in detail, once you see that it's not just arbitrary deformity, once you understand what you are really looking at are the outcomes of the laws that regulate and make the human body. When this happens, deformity acquires a real beauty. It's a beauty that emerges from answering one of the oldest questions in biology: namely, how are we put together?

~~~

But that's intellectual beauty. What of human physical beauty? This is something that interests me greatly. I'm not interested in the general aesthetic question here, but ourselves. Some people say that beauty is uninteresting and that it's just a matter of taste. I don't think so. I would say, and there are others who would certainly agree with me, that we have a general psychological program from which stems a universal notion of beauty. Incidentally, this idea that we all perceive certain features to be beautiful is one that Darwin would have disagreed with. Darwin believed that the perception of beauty was particular to particular peoples in particular times and places. He was probably wrong, or at least he was only partly right. I won't attempt to justify that answer, but I think it to be true. These days, the general thinking tends to be that there's a universal notion of beauty which is true for people around the world. And the question is, what is that and what drives it?

Many people think that beauty is a certificate of health; this is an idea that comes out of sociobiology. But it is more obvious than than that. It's simply the idea that beautiful people are healthy people and we search for healthy mates. And that's probably true. Or at least it was. But is it still? In the past, health was primarily a matter of environmental conditions—your exposure to contagious diseases and the amount of food that you had when you were growing up. Rich people had better environments, hence the positive association between beauty and wealth. But what of modern economically egalitarian societies such as Holland? In such societies, does the ancient association still obtain? If the variance in beauty is due to the variance in the quality of the rearing environment then it must be the case that the Dutch — who all eat much the same good food, live in much the same well-designed houses, and have access to much the same excellent health-care — must all be equivalently beautiful. But is this so? The answer is, of course, no. Among the Dutch you can find good-looking and not so good-looking people. And the question is then, why?

I would argue that the reason for this is that there is and will always be variance in beauty is because there is variance in mutational load. What is beauty fundamentally about? I would argue — and this is really just a postulate at this time, but it is one that interests me a great deal — that the fundamental reason why some of us are more beautiful than others is because of those deleterious mutations that we all carry We may carry 300 deleterious mutations on average, but there is of course a variance associated with that. Not everybody has 300. Some people have more, some people have fewer. If this is true—and statistically it must be true — then someone in the world has the fewest mutations of all. Someone in the world is the least mutant human of all. Indeed, we can actually calculate, making some assumptions about the shape of the distribution, how many mutations that person has — and it turns out to be 191 versus the average of 300. This, to my mind, is surprisingly many. I would suggest that if we could find that person, he or she would be a good candidate for being the most beautiful person in the world. At least she would be, assuming she did not grow up in some impoverished underdeveloped nation. Which, statistically, she will have done since most people do.

~~~

There's one more thing that I should like to know about, and that is the nature of normal human variety. There are tens of thousands of geneticists around the world, all of whom are busy identifying the genes that cause human disorders of one sort or another. Historically they began with the really easy ones, the big congenital disorders, especially those that allow people to survive and produce children and so have big pedigrees that allow them to map the genes. Now the emphasis has shifted to studying the genetic basis of more subtle and more complicated kinds of disorders, things like diabetes and cancer, that have lots of genes that underlie them each of which has a small effect. This is a much more difficult task, but people are doing it because these are the inherited diseases that affect millions.

But there's one aspect of human inheritance that people are resolutely ignoring. And that is normal human variety. Or, to put it more crisply: race. If we look around the world we find that people look very different from each other. These differences are manifestly genetic. They must be. That's why people's kids look like them. Yet we know nothing about that variety. We don't know what the differences are between white skin and black skin, European skin versus African skin. What I mean is we don't know what the genetic basis of that is. This is actually amazing. I mean, here's a trait, trivial as it may be, about which wars have been fought, which is one of the great fault lines in society, around which people construct their identities as nothing else. And yet we haven't the foggiest idea what the genetic basis of this is. It's amazing. Why is that?

The reason is two-fold. The first—which is not such a trivial problem—is that skin colour is not controlled by one gene. If it were only one gene we'd know it. It's many genes—more than three but certainly fewer than 30. It's a difficult problem, although, frankly, it's not such a difficult problem that if geneticists really wanted to solve it, they couldn't. It'd be easy enough to do if they put a fraction of the effort that went into discovering the BRCA1, the breast cancer gene. I'm not saying they should; finding the breast cancer gene is more important than discovering the genetic basis of white and black skin, but still, it's not a technically impossible thing to do.

But of course the fundamental reason why people don't do it is because it's race genetics. It's because of the long and sorry history of genetics and racial differences. And indeed, more than that, the whole thrust of genetics since the war has been to argue that races don't exist and that they are just social constructs. This is very much the Harvard School — Dick Lewontin for example has been one of the big proponents of this point of view. The late Stephen Jay Gould was another.

After the Second World War, when the enormities of Nazi science really hit home — which were in turn the consequence of a much larger racial science, not just in Germany, but everywhere—all right-thinking scientists made a resolute effort to ensure that science would not be bent to such evil purposes again. They were determined that science would never again be used to make invidious discriminations among people. The immediate result of this was the UNESCO Declaration on Race in 1950, fronted by Ashley Montagu and backed up by geneticists such as Theodosius Dobzhansky which affirmed the equality of races. Then, in the 1960s, Dick Lewontin and others discovered that gel electrophoresis could be used to survey genetic variation among proteins. These studies showed that humans have a huge amount of concealed genetic variation. What is more, most of that genetic variation existed within continents or even countries rather than among them. UNESCO said races were equal; the new genetics said they didn't exist. Finally, moving a few decades on, the Out-of-Africa hypothesis of the origin of Homo sapiens comes to the fore, and multi-regionalism falls from fashion as it becomes clear that humans are not only a single species — something which we've known since Linnaeus' day—but a single species that has only diverged into sub-populations very recently.

The result of this history — which has been partly driven by data, and partly by ideology — is that these days anthropologists and geneticists overwhelmingly emphasise the similarities among people from different parts of the world at the expense of the differences. From a political point of view I have no doubt that's a fine thing. But I suggest that it's time that we grew up. I would like to suggest that actually by emphasizing the similarities but ignoring the differences, we are turning away from one of the most beautiful problems that modern biology has left: namely, what is the genetic basis of the normal variety of differences between us? What gives a Han Chinese child the curve of her eye? The curve I read once described by an eminent Sinologist as the purest of all curves. What is the source of that curve? And what gives a Solomon Islander his black-verging-on-purple skin? Or what makes red hair?

Actually, the last is the one thing we do know. It turns out that red hair is due to a mutation in a gene called MC1R, melanocortin receptor 1, which controls the production of p eumelanin, black pigment, versus red pigment, phaeomelanin. Rather marvellously, it also turns out that mutations in MCIR also cause red hair in red setters, Scottish cattle, and red foxes. But we don't know what causes brown eyes versus blue eyes versus green eyes. We know very little about the variation in normal human height. We don't know why some girls have big breasts and some of them have small breasts. These are important questions — or at least jolly interesting ones—and we just don't know their answers.

The reason I love the problem of normal human variety is because, almost uniquely among modern scientific problems, it is a problem that we can apprehend as we walk down the street. We live in an age now where the deepest scientific problems are buried away from our immediate perception. They concern the origin of the universe. They concern the relationships of subatomic particles. They concern the nature and structure of the human genome. Nobody can see these things without large bits of expensive equipment. But when I consider the problem of human variety I feel as Aristotle must have felt when he first walked down to the shore at Lesvos for the first time. The world is new again. What is more, it is a problem that we can now solve, a question we can now answer. And I think we should.

Of course, there will be people who object. There will be people who will say that this is a revival of racial science. Perhaps so. I would argue, however, that even if this is a revival of racial science, we should engage in it for it does not follow that it is a revival of racist science. Indeed, I would argue, that it is just the opposite. How shall I put it? If you want to prove, what most of us believe, that skin colour does not give the measure of a man, that it tells nothing about his abilities or temperament—then surely the best way is to learn about the genetics of skin colour and the genetics of cognitive ability and demonstrate that they have nothing to do with each other? The point is that there will always be people who wish to construct socially unjust theories about racial differences. And though it is true that science can be bent to evil ends, it is more often the case that injustice creeps in through the cracks of our ignorance than anything else. It is to finally close off those cracks that we should be studying the genetic basis of human variety.



JAMES J. O'DONNELL
Classicist; Provost, Georgetown University; Author, Avatars of the Word: From Papyrus to Cyberspace

From the Enlightenment forward, it has been assumed that good science is the instrument of good politics. Science disabuses us of error and shows that bad politics are undergirded by falsehood.

But what if good politics turn out to be undergirded by falsehood? Then the honest and honorable supporters of science are tempted to suppress, modify, or veil in discreet silence the discoveries of science -- or even the questions that scientists would ask. That is a dangerous temptation, because the enemies of good science are still all around us, promoting notions of "intelligent design" (to argue that while the deity may have the taste, talent, and ingenuity of Rube Goldberg in the things he creates, at least he exists) and opposing lines of research that offend ancient proscriptions.

The answer is better science, better reporting about science, and bravery. The future of genetics will surely reveal differences between and among groups of people that overlap with stereotypes, prejudices, and myths. Some of those developments will appear to reinforce bigotry: so be it, as far as that goes, but the important thing is to communicate a science that continues to move forwards. In the 1950s, going heavy on the margarine and light on the eggs seemed the apex of science regarding cholesterol and heart attack risk. Now the margarine of those days appears itself to be a killer. Similarly, the genetic discovery today, while true, will also likely be at a greater level of generality than what we will know in 10 or 20 years.

That's why it will take bravery: to tell the truth now, to persist in research, to oppose people who draw stupid conclusions from good science, and to make better science.

ANDREW BROWN
Journalist, the Guardian; Author, In the Beginning Was the Worm: Finding the Secrets of Life in a Tiny Hermaphrodite

Yes, of course the genetics of human diversity are interesting, and some scientists are interested in them for disinterested motives. But I think it is unfair to Gould to suppose that there are only bad reasons to be leery of this interest, and unfair to Lewontin to suppose that there is anything very much more illuminating or important that we can say than that race is a social construction even if we can find genetic clusters which would, as Armand Leroi suggests, allow a geneticist to look at a sample of my spit and tell from it where all my great great grandparents lived.

In defence of Gould, I would say that of course a little knowledge is a dangerous thing; and the best cure for dangerous knowledge is more and better knowledge. However, there is no guarantee that we will find this further knowledge quickly or at all; while we are looking, great harm may be done with the dangerous and partial stuff. There is nothing unreasonable in wishing that certain discoveries had never been made. Some people would consider lobotomy, or even Freudian psychoanalysis cases in point. I am certain that any research in to human genetic differences will be seized on by racist scientists and racists generally. Whether you think an advance in knowledge is worth this cost is a political judgement with no obvious or final answer.

The Left is often accused of groundless optimism about human nature. In this case Gould was pessimistic and his grounds for pessimism seem reasonable to me. If you look at the way that science is twisted and abused in the current American debates on climate change and creationism, it's difficult to feel that a public debate on the reality of race will be conducted in a spirit of disinterested longing for truth.

But let's look at the sort of knowledge that Leroi wants. The genetics of skin colour are interesting and could perhaps be worked out quite quickly. The genetics of breast shape are possibly even more interesting and I'm sure you could get funding to study them. But the real fascination and the real tabus surround the genetics of intelligence and behaviour. If these turned out to vary between races, as it appears they vary between sexes, we would have a sensational scientific discovery.

Now, one of the points about this list is that the more interesting these qualities are, the harder it is to read them out from the genome. Breast shape may be produced by genes and nutrition, but what constitutes a desirable shape has varied greatly in the last fifty years, and the kind of nutrition that fashionable women allow themselves has varied with this preference too. Similarly, the kinds of intelligence, and the kinds of behaviour, that are rewarded and considered desirable in children, have changed a great deal in the last hundred years, and will presumably change a great deal in the next century too. To call some human trait "socially constructed" doesn't mean we can change it at will; and it certainly doesn't mean there is no genetic component.

This comes out clearly in the classic Wilson/Daly studies of homicide rates. These show there must be a strong genetic component to our species' homicidal behaviour, simply because the pattern stays constant across widely differing societies with widely differing homicide rates. But the evidence which shows us this also shows that changing the environment can hugely diminish the rate at which young men do in fact kill each other. Which half of the story is more important?

Still, we can be certain that the research will be done. Some new things will be found, and on an individual level, they will be important and useful. We will know more about genetic variations among human groups, and we may, just possibly, discover more about the genetics of behaviour and intelligence and how they vary. On that subject we could hardly know less than we do now. The real question is how these two kinds of knowledge will fit together. Will there be any correlation between the clusters of genes that control appearance, which do undoubtedly exist, presumably as a result of sexual selection; and other gene clusters, as yet undiscovered, which affect intelligence and behaviour? It is these second clusters that people are really interested in, and here there is no evidence to suggest that Lewontin's results are misleading and that the variations are greater within races than between them (and that the greatest variation is found in Africa). But we won't know for a very long time because we don't know which genes are involved and even whether they cluster.

In the mean time, all those people who already think they know what "race" means will be convinced that science has proved them right. They will twist the work of decent scientists like Leroi to indecent ends. Gould himself had this happen to him when creationists abused his work on punctuated equilibrium. Only if you think that racism is, in the modern world, less widespread than creationism can you laugh at the spectacle of Gould's ghost wringing his hands.


TIM D. WHITE
Paleontologist; Co-director Middle Awash Human Origins and Evolution
Project

Human Variety: Evolution's Creation

Armand Leroi's points are made stronger by adding the dimension of time. Countries and races may seem ancient and fixed without the perspectives of history and evolutionary biology. It is sobering to consider that only fifteen generations separate us from Washington, Jefferson and Napoleon.

Ten thousand generations ago, a man died at the edge of a tropical African lake. The place, now called Herto, is in today's Ethiopia. We now know Herto man by the tools his people fashioned from volcanic rock, and by his skull. His skin was almost certainly dark, but a forensic scientist would be baffled by the shape of the man's skull. It clearly belongs to our species Homo sapiens, but it defies attribution to a specific modern human group.

Whether measured in geological or evolutionary terms, Herto man didn't live very long ago. After all, the well-known Australopithecus female "Lucy" was born nearby, but she had died about 200,000 generations before Herto man was even conceived. By any reckoning, our species is a youngster among hominids, primates, and mammals.

The Herto man lived at the same time that European neanderthals (presumably light-skinned) inhabited a landscape refrigerated by the penultimate glaciation. Therefore, when combined with studies on modern human and neanderthal DNA, it is clear that Pleistocene Earth witnessed hominid biological variation at the species level.

Human evolutionists have long known that today's one-hominid planet is an anomaly rather than the rule. And racial variation would certainly have characterized any of the hominid species spread across major segments of the Old World. We can already dimly perceive a bit of that sub-specific variation in the skeletal fragments already recovered, but we can still only imagine the soft tissue features that would have distinguished Iberian, Malayan and Somalian Homo erectus.

But when did geographic diversity arise within Homo sapiens? By baffling the forensic scientist, the Herto man gives us a clue. His skull is shaped more like a modern Australian aboriginal than a modern Ethiopian, but no modern human matches it exactly.

So the 160,000-year-old Herto cranium shows us that the skeletal features allowing contemporary forensic scientists to differentiate today's Africans from Europeans or Asians had not yet evolved, even at this late date in human evolution. Confirmation comes from studies of the modern human Y-chromosome and mitochondrial DNA. These suggest that the common roots of the human species are very shallow compared to the vast majority of other mammalian species. Whether considered paleontologically or genetically, it appears that much of the physical variation to which Armand Leroi draws our attention evolved during the last little bit of our more-than-six-million-year tenure as a lineage separate from the African chimpanzees.

Like Marco Polo, Herodotus and Columbus, we all recognize that modern human physical variation is geographically patterned. Was this always the case? No, most fundamentally because we were not always modern humans! Phenotypic variation among primates results primarily from Darwinian selection, mate choice, and genetic drift. Our molecules and the fossilized bones of our ancestors indicate that our roots are shallow relative to other mammalian species. Our anatomical and physiological variation inform us about the where and when of our origins.

Our genes, our bodies, and the racial variation in our young species are not social constructs. Rather, these are all the products of evolutionary forces operating over the last couple of hundred millennia. Understanding any of them requires the unique perspective of evolutionary biology.


ALUN ANDERSON
Editor-in-Chief, Publishing Director, New Scientist.

Armand Leroi is bound to please the right wingers with his view that "genetic data show that races clearly do exist". I'm sure that is not his intention but I also doubt that everyone will read as far as his belief that "skin colour does not give the measure of a man, that it tells nothing about his abilities or temperament". That genetics has a bad history of being misunderstood and misapplied scarcely needs restating.

Leroi's call for a better understanding of the genetics of human diversity is welcome. Whether everyone would classify "we don't know why some girls have big breasts and some of them have small breasts" as an "important question", I'm less than sure although it may be one that will attract novel sources of research funding! More generally, knowing more about diversity might settle the question of whether "beauty" is really an expression of biological fitness and that would certainly be worth knowing.

Trying to resurrect race is much less worthwhile. All that has really happened in recent years is that some geneticists have realised that if you measure a number of different genetic differences between people you can then cluster these differences into groups that broadly mirror our common sense notion of race. This is not really too surprising as we would anticipate that if we can make a reasonable guess about someone's origins then must be some set of genetic differences underlying them.

The trouble is that these genetic clusters are not that well defined, still muddle up some people with quite different origins, and have not been associated with anything deep or fundamental about people of different origins. Leroi pretty much says so himself. To fill out the quote above, Leroi says in full that "Some [contributors to the journal Nature Genetics] argued that, looked at the right way, genetic data show that races clearly do exist". Elsewhere we find "Race is merely a shorthand that enables us to speak sensibly, though with no great precision, about genetic rather than cultural or political differences". Leroi at first appears to support the view that classifying people by "race" would at least make it possible to "improve medical care" by tailoring treatment to race. But he quickly goes on to say that: "Everyone agrees that race is a crude way of predicting who gets some disease or responds to some treatment".

Indeed so, for a focus on race can blind doctors to groupings that cut across racial lines. Sickle cell anaemia, for example, is often regarded as an African disease but occurs in a number of groups around the world. Nor would a broad classification based on "racial categories" tell you that Ashkenazi Jews, for example, are prone to a rare mutation that causes breast cancer. These issues have been explored in some depth in New Scientist.

Race is too crude and too shallow a concept to be worth resurrecting even as a scientific shorthand and has already done too much harm. In medicine, it is the individual genotypes determining disease susceptibility and drug reactions that are worth pursuing. If we would like to know more about diversity—why some people have straight and some have curly hair, for example—classifying broad racial clusters does not really help us to find the answer.

Although in my view Leroi overstates the case for race as a useful concept, I still applaud him for speaking about diversity and biology. At a recent session I chaired at the World Economic Forum in Switzerland on Gender and the Brain, the real anger came from US scientists and intellectuals, venting their frustration that any discussion of biological differences relating to sex or race is a forbidden zone in universities in America. Although this session occurred at the height of the controversy over Larry Summers's poorly thought out remarks on female scientists, which certainly raised temperatures, it does indeed seem an indicator, as Leroi put it, that "it's time that we grew up".


NICHOLAS HUMPHREY
Psychologist, London School of Economics; Author, The Mind Made Flesh

Let me change the subject away from race, to Leroi's provocative remarks about beauty and deformity.

Here's the problem. If the most beautiful person in the world is whoever it is who carries the fewest fitness lowering mutations, then (other things being equal) presumably the most beautiful person in the world is also the fittest person in the world. But this begs the question. Is she the fittest because she is regarded by potential mates as the most beautiful (and therefore gets to choose the best possible of fathers for her children). Or is she regarded as the most beautiful because she is seen by potential mates as the fittest (and therefore gets to be chosen by them as the best possible mother for their children).

Either way, I worry about Leroi's assumption that maximal beauty does in fact equal maximal fitness. There are many reasons why, as matter of fact, great beauty may not lead to great reproductive success. W.B. Yeats pointed to more than one of these when, in his "Prayer for his Daughter," he prayed for her to have beauty but not too much of it.

May she be granted beauty and yet not
Beauty to make a stranger's eye distraught,
Or hers before a looking-glass, for such,
Being made beautiful overmuch,
Consider beauty a sufficient end,
Lose natural kindness and maybe
The heart-revealing intimacy
That chooses right, and never find a friend.

Still more to the point, in the context of Leroi's discussion of deformity, sometimes an admixture of ugliness — even of deformity — can be a positive asset in its own right. For the fact is that individuals who start life with a disadvantage, and who are obliged to compensate as best they can, may come up with alternative ways of doing things that leave them ahead of the game. Lord Byron, who is said to have had a club foot, drew attention to this paradoxical aspect of deformity in a remarkable poem, "The Deformed Transformed."

... Deformity is daring.
It is its essence to o'ertake mankind
By heart and soul, and make itself the equal —
Aye, the superior of the rest. There is
A spur in its halt movements, to become
All that the others cannot, in such things
As still are free to both, to compensate
For stepdame Nature's avarice.

Thus even "deleterious mutations" can prove a blessing in disguise. Of course no doubt Leroi would say in that case they don't count as "deleterious." But this is an old move. As Sir John Harrington pointed out, on the subject of "Treason.":

Treason is ne'er successful
Here's the reason:
When it's successful,
Then it's not called "treason."

EDGE BOOKS


Curious Minds: How a Child Becomes a Scientist (Pantheon)

All new essays by 27 leading Edge contributors..."Good, narrative history, combined with much fine writing...quirky, absorbing and persuasive in just the way that good stories are."—Nature "Some of the biggest brains in the world turn their lenses on their own lives...fascinating...an invigorating debate."—Washington Post "Compelling."—Discover " An engrossing treat of a book...crammed with hugely enjoyable anecdotes ...you'll have a wonderful time reading these reminiscences."New Scientist "An intriguing collection of essays detailing the childhood experiences of prominent scientists and the life events that sparked their hunger for knowledge. Full of comical and thought-provoking stories."Globe & Mail "An inspiring collection of 27 essays by leading scientists about the childhood moments that set them on their shining paths."—Psychology Today

Published in the UK as When We Were Kids: How a Child Becomes a Scientist (Jonathan Cape)

amazon.com
| b&n.com | amazon.co.uk


The New Humanists: Science at the Edge (Barnes & Noble)

The best of Edge, now available in a book..."Provocative and fascinating." La Stampa "A stellar cast of thinkers tackles the really big questions facing scientists."The Guardian "A compact, if bumpy, tour through the minds of some of the world's preeminent players in science and technology." — Philadelphia Inquirer "What a show they put on!"— San Jose Mercury News "a very important contribution, sparkling and polychromatic."Corriere della Sera

Published in the UK as Science at the Edge (Weidenfeld)
Available at Barnes & Noble stores | b&n.com | amazon.co.uk


The Next Fifty Years:
Science in the First Half of the Twenty-first Century
(Vintage)

Original essays by 25 of the world's leading scientists..."Entertaining" —New Scientist "Provocative" —Daily Telegraph "Inspired"—Wired "Mind-stretching" —Times Higher Education Supplement "Fascinating"Dallas Morning News "Dazzling" —Washington Post Book World


John Brockman, Editor and Publisher
Russell Weinberger, Associate Publisher

contact: [email protected]
Copyright © 2005 by
Edge Foundation, Inc
All Rights Reserved.

|Top|