|
Edge
160— May 10, 2005 |
CONTENTS |
|
EDGE 160 |
![]() |
THE SCIENCE OF GENDER AND SCIENCE PINKER VS. SPELKE A
DEBATE
...on the research on mind, brain, and behavior that may be relevant to gender disparities in the sciences, including the studies of bias, discrimination and innate and acquired difference between the sexes. Harvard
University • Mind/Brain/Behavior Initiative The Mind Brain and Behavior Inter-Faculty Initiative (MBB), under the leadership of Co-Directors Marc D. Hauser and Elizabeth Spelke, is a university-wide community that studies the structure, function, evolution, development, and pathology of the nervous system, in relation to decision-making and behavior. Introduction On April 22, 2005, Harvard University's Mind/Brain/Behavior Initiative (MBB) held a defining debate on the public discussion that began on January 16th with the public comments by Lawrence Summers, president of Harvard, on sex differences between men and women and how they may relate to the careers of women in science. The debate at MBB, "The Gender of Gender and Science" was "on the research on mind, brain, and behavior that may be relevant to gender disparities in the sciences, including the studies of bias, discrimination and innate and acquired difference between the sexes". It's interesting to note that since the controversy surrounding Summers' remarks began, there has been an astonishing absence of discussion of the relevant science...you won't find it in the hundreds and hundreds of articles in major newspapers; nor will find it in the Harvard faculty meetings where the president of the leading University in America was indicted for presenting controversial ideas. Scientists debate continually, and reality is the check. They may have egos as large as those possessed by the iconic figures of the academic humanities, but they handle their hubris in a very different way. They can be moved by arguments, because they work in an empirical world of facts, a world based on reality. There are no fixed, unalterable positions. They are both the creators and the critics of their shared enterprise. Ideas come from them and they also criticize one another's ideas. Through the process of creativity and criticism and debates, they decide which ideas get weeded out and which become part of the consensus that leads to the next level of discovery. But unlike just about anything else said about Summers' remarks, the debate, "The Science of Gender and Science", between Harvard psychology professors Steven Pinker and Elizabeth Spelke, focused on the relevant scientific literature. It was both interesting on facts but differing in interpretation. Both presented scientific evidence with the realization and understanding that there was nothing obvious about how the data was to be interpreted. Their sharp scientific debate informed rather than detracted. And it showed how a leading University can still fulfill its role of providing a forum for free and open discussion on controversial subjects in a fair-minded way. It also had the added benefit that the participants knew what they were talking about. Who won the debate? Make up your own mind. Watch the video, listen to the audio, read the text and check out the slide presentations. There's a lesson here: let's get it right and when we do we will adjust our attitudes. That's what science can do, and that's what Edge offers by presenting Pinker vs. Spelke to a wide public audience. STEVEN PINKER is the Johnstone Family Professor in the Department of Psychology at Harvard University. His research has won prizes from the National Academy of Sciences and the Royal Institution of Great Britain, and he is the author of six books, including The Language Instinct, How the Mind Works, Words and Rules, and The Blank Slate. ELIZABETH S. SPELKE is Berkman Professor of Psychology at Harvard University, where she is Co-Director of the Mind, Brain, and Behavior Initiative. A member of the National Academy of Sciences and the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, she is cited by Time Magazine as one of America's Best in Science and Medicine. Elizabeth Spelke's Edge Bio Page ![]() THE
SCIENCE OF GENDER AND SCIENCE [EDITOR'S NOTE: Pinker and Spelke each made presentations of about 40 minutes, without interruption, from each other or from the audience. They then responded to each other's presentations. By mutual agreement, Pinker made the first presentation. This Edge presentation includes: the transcribed text; streaming audio of the full debate; 6-minute video clips from Pinker and Spelke's opening statements; a 20-minute video clip of the their closing discussion; and online versions of the speakers' slide presentations. There are two options for viewing the slides: Clicking on the links immediately below brings up the file of either Pinker or Spelke's complete slide presentation. Or, the individual slides are also included for reference as expandable thumbnails in the margin of the transcript.]
|
(STEVEN
PINKER:) Thanks,
Liz, for agreeing to this exchange. It's a privilege to be engaged
in a conversation with Elizabeth Spelke. We go back a long way. We
have been colleagues at MIT, where I helped attract her, and at Harvard,
where she helped to attract me. With the rest of my field, I have
enormous admiration for Elizabeth's brilliant contributions to our
understanding of the origins of cognition. But we do find ourselves
with different perspectives on a recent issue. |
|||
For those
of you who just arrived from Mars, there has been a certain amount
of discussion here at Harvard on a particular datum, namely the under-representation
of women among tenure-track faculty in elite universities in physical
science, math, and engineering. Here are some recent numbers: |
|||
![]() |
As with
many issues in psychology, there are three broad ways to explain this
phenomenon. One can imagine an extreme "nature" position: that males
but not females have the talents and temperaments necessary for science.
Needless to say, only a madman could take that view. The extreme nature
position has no serious proponents. |
||
![]() |
There is an extreme "nurture" position: that males and females are biologically indistinguishable, and all relevant sex differences are products of socialization and bias. Then there
are various intermediate positions: that the difference is explainable
by some combination of biological differences in average temperaments
and talents interacting with socialization and bias. |
||
![]() |
Liz has
embraced the extreme nurture position. There is an irony here, because
in most discussions in cognitive science she and I are put in the same
camp, namely the "innatists," when it comes to explaining the mind. But
in this case Liz has said that there is "not a shred of evidence" for
the biological factor, that "the evidence against there being
an advantage for males in intrinsic aptitude is so overwhelming that
it is hard for me to see how one can make a case at this point on the
other side," and that "it seems to me as conclusive as any
finding I know of in science." |
||
![]() |
Well we certainly aren't seeing the stereotypical gender difference in confidence here! Now, I'm a controversial guy. I've taken many controversial positions over the years, and, as a member of Homo sapiens, I think I am right on all of them. But I don't think that in any of them I would say there is "not a shred of evidence" for the other side, even if I think that the evidence favors one side. I would not say that the other side "can't even make a case" for their position, even if I think that their case is not as good as the one I favor. And as for saying that a position is "as conclusive as any finding in science" — well, we're talking about social science here! This statement would imply that the extreme nurture position on gender differences is more conclusive than, say the evidence that the sun is at the center of the solar system, for the laws of thermodynamics, for the theory of evolution, for plate tectonics, and so on. These are
extreme statements — especially in light of the fact that an
enormous amount of research, summarized in these and many other literature
reviews, in fact points to a very different conclusion. I'll quote
from one of them, a book called Sex Differences in Cognitive Ability by
Diane Halpern. She is a respected psychologist, recently elected as
president of the American Psychological Association, and someone with
no theoretical axe to grind. She does not subscribe to any particular
theory, and has been a critic, for example, of evolutionary psychology.
And here what she wrote in the preface to her book: |
||
![]() ![]() |
|
||
![]() |
This captures my assessment perfectly. Again for the benefit of the Martians in this room: This isn't just any old issue in empirical psychology. There are obvious political colorings to it, and I want to begin with a confession of my own politics. I am a feminist. I believe that women have been oppressed, discriminated against, and harassed for thousands of years. I believe that the two waves of the feminist movement in the 20th century are among the proudest achievements of our species, and I am proud to have lived through one of them, including the effort to increase the representation of women in the sciences. But it
is crucial to distinguish the moral proposition that people
should not be discriminated against on account of their sex — which
I take to be the core of feminism — and the empirical claim
that males and females are biologically indistinguishable. They are
not the same thing. Indeed, distinguishing them is essential to protecting
the core of feminism. Anyone who takes an honest interest in science
has to be prepared for the facts on a given issue to come out either
way. And that makes it essential that we not hold the ideals of feminism
hostage to the latest findings from the lab or field. Otherwise, if
the findings come out as showing a sex difference, one would either
have to say, "I guess sex discrimination wasn't so bad after all," or
else furiously suppress or distort the findings so as to preserve the ideal. The truth cannot
be sexist. Whatever the facts turn out to be, they should not be taken
to compromise the core of feminism. |
||
![]() |
Why study sex differences? Believe me, being the Bobby Riggs of cognitive science is not my idea of a good time. So should I care about them, especially since they are not the focus of my own research? First, differences between the sexes are part of the human condition. We all have a mother and a father. Most of us are attracted to members of the opposite sex, and the rest of us notice the difference from those who do. And we can't help but notice the sex of our children, friends, and our colleagues, in every aspect of life. Also, the
topic of possible sex differences is of great scientific interest.
Sex is a fundamental problem in biology, and sexual reproduction and
sex differences go back a billion years. There's an interesting theory,
which I won't have time to explain, which predicts that there should
be an overall equal investment of organisms in their sons and daughters;
neither sex is predicted to be superior or inferior across the board.
There is also an elegant theory, namely Bob Trivers' theory of differential
parental investment, which makes highly specific predictions about
when you should expect sex differences and what they should look like. |
||
The nature and source of sex differences are also of practical importance. Most of us agree that there are aspects of the world, including gender disparities, that we want to change. But if we want to change the world we must first understand it, and that includes understanding the sources of sex differences. Let's get back to the datum to be explained. In many ways this is an exotic phenomenon. It involves biologically unprepared talents and temperaments: evolution certainly did not shape any part of the mind to do the work of a professor of mechanical engineering at MIT, for example. The datum has nothing to do with basic cognitive processes, or with those we use in our everyday lives, in school, or even in most college courses, where indeed there are few sex differences. Also, we are talking about extremes of achievement. Most women are not qualified to be math professors at Harvard because most men aren't qualified to be math professors at Harvard. These are extremes in the population. And we're talking about a subset of fields. Women are no under-represented to nearly the same extent in all academic fields, and certainly not in all prestigious professions. Finally,
we are talking about a statistical effect. This is such a crucial point
that I have to discuss it in some detail. |
|||
![]() |
Women are nowhere near absent even from the field in which they are most under-represented. The explanations for sex differences must be statistical as well. And here is a touchstone for the entire discussion: These are
two Gaussian or normal distributions; two bell curves. The X axis stands
for any ability you want to measure. The Yaxis stands for the proportion
of people having that ability. The overlapping curves are what you
get whenever you compare the sexes on any measure in which they differ.
In this example, if we say that this is the male curve and this is
the female curve, the means may be different, but at any particular
ability level there are always representatives of both genders. |
||
![]() |
So right
away a number of public statements that have been made last couple
of months can be seen as red herrings, and should never have been made
by anyone who understands the nature of statistical distributions.
This includes the accusation that President Summers implied that "50%
of the brightest minds in America do not have the right aptitude for
science," that "women just can't cut it," and so on. These statements
are statistically illiterate, and have nothing to do with the phenomena
we are discussing. |
||
![]() ![]() ![]() |
There are
some important corollaries of having two overlapping normal distributions.
One is that a normal distribution falls off according to the negative
exponential of the square of the distance from the mean. That
means that even when there is only a small difference in the means
of two distributions, the more extreme a score, the greater the disparity
there will be in the two kinds of individuals having such a score.
That is, the ratios get more extreme as you go farther out along the
tail. If we hold a magnifying glass to the tail of the distribution,
we see that even though the distributions overlap in the bulk of the
curves, when you get out to the extremes the difference between the
two curves gets larger and larger. |
||
![]() |
For example,
it's obvious that distributions of height for men and women overlap:
it's not the case that all men are taller than all women. But while
at five foot ten there are thirty men for every woman, at six feet
there are two thousand men for every woman. Now, sex differences
in cognition tend not to be so extreme, but the statistical phenomenon
is the same. |
||
![]() ![]() |
A
second important corollary is that tail ratios are affected by differences
in variance. And biologists since Darwin have noted that for many traits
and many species, males are the more variable gender. So even in cases
where the mean for women and the mean for men are the same, the fact
that men are more variable implies that the proportion of men would be
higher at one tail, and also higher at the other. As it's sometimes summarized:
more prodigies, more idiots. |
||
![]() |
With these statistical points in mind, let me begin the substance of my presentation by connecting the political issue with the scientific one. Economists who study patterns of discrimination have long argued (generally to no avail) that there is a crucial conceptual difference between difference and discrimination. A departure from a 50-50 sex ratio in any profession does not, by itself, imply that we are seeing discrimination, unless the interests and aptitudes of the two groups are equated. Let me illustrate the point with an example, involving myself. I work in a scientific field — the study of language acquisition in children — that is in fact dominated by women. Seventy-five percent of the members the main professional association are female, as are a majority of the keynote speakers at our main conference. I'm here to tell you that it's not because men like me have been discriminated against. I decided to study language development, as opposed to, say, mechanical engineering, for many reasons. The goal of designing a better automobile transmission does not turn me on as much as the goal of figuring out how kids acquire language. And I don't think I'd be as good at designing a transmission as I am in studying child language. Now, all
we need to do to explain sex differences without invoking the discrimination
or invidious sexist comparisons is to suppose that whatever traits I have
that predispose me to choose (say) child language over (say)
mechanical engineering are not exactly equally distributed statistically
among men and women. For those of you out there — of either gender — who
also are not mechanical engineers, you should understand what I'm talking
about. |
||
![]() |
Okay,
so what are the similarities and differences between the sexes?
There certainly are many similarities. Men and women show no differences
in general intelligence or g — on average, they are exactly
the same, right on the money. Also, when it comes to the basic categories
of cognition — how we negotiate the world and live our lives; our
concept of objects, of numbers, of people, of living things, and so on — there
are no differences. |
||
![]() |
Indeed, in cases where there are differences, there are as many instances in which women do slightly better than men as ones in which men do slightly better than women. For example, men are better at throwing, but women are more dexterous. Men are better at mentally rotating shapes; women are better at visual memory. Men are better at mathematical problem-solving; women are better at mathematical calculation. And so on. But there
are at least six differences that are relevant to the datum we have
been discussing. The literature on these differences is so enormous
that I can only touch on a fraction of it. I'll restrict my discussion
to a few examples in which there are enormous data sets, or there
are meta-analyses that boil down a literature. |
||
![]() |
The first
difference, long noted by economists studying employment practices,
is that men and women differ in what they state are their priorities
in life. To sum it up: men, on average, are more likely to chase status
at the expense of their families; women give a more balanced weighting.
Once again: Think statistics! The finding is not that women value family
and don't value status. It is not that men value status and don't value
family. Nor does the finding imply that every last woman has the asymmetry
that women show on average or that every last man has the asymmetry
that men show on average. But in large data sets, on average, an asymmetry
what you find. |
||
![]() |
Just
one example. In a famous long-term study of mathematically precocious
youth, 1,975 youngsters were selected in 7th grade for being in the top
1% of ability in mathematics, and then followed up for more than two
decades. These men and women are certainly equally talented. And
if anyone has ever been encouraged in math and science, these kids were.
Both genders: they are equal in their levels of achievement, and they
report being equally satisfied with the course of their lives. Nonetheless
there are statistical differences in what they say is important to them.
There are some things in life that the females rated higher than males,
such as the ability to have a part-time career for a limited time in
one's life; living close to parents and relatives; having a meaningful
spiritual life; and having strong friendships. And there are some things
in life that the males rated higher than the females. They include having
lots of money; inventing or creating something; having a full-time career;
and being successful in one's line of work. It's worth noting that studies
of highly successful people find that single-mindedness and competitiveness
are recurring traits in geniuses (of both sexes). |
||
![]() |
Here
is one other figure from this data set. As you might expect, this sample
has a lot of people who like to work Herculean hours. Many people in
this group say they would like to work 50, 60, even 70 hours a week.
But there are also slight differences. At each one of these high numbers
of hours there are slightly more men than women who want to work that
much. That is, more men than women don't care about whether they have
a life. |
||
![]() |
Second,
interest in people versus things and abstract rule systems. There is
a staggering amount of data on this trait, because there is an
entire field that studies people's vocational interests. I bet most of
the people in this room have taken a vocational interest test at some
point in their lives. And this field has documented that there are consistent
differences in the kinds of activities that appeal to men and women in
their ideal jobs. I'll just discuss one of them: the desire to work with
people versus things. There is an enormous average difference between
women and men in this dimension, about one standard deviation. |
||
![]() |
And this difference in interests will tend to cause people to gravitate in slightly different directions in their choice of career. The occupation that fits best with the "people" end of the continuum is "director of a community services organization." The occupations that fit best with the "things" end are physicist, chemist, mathematician, computer programmer, and biologist. We see
this consequence not only in the choice of whether to go into science,
but also in the choice which branch of science the two sexes tend
to go into. Needless to say, from 1970 to 2002 there was a huge increase
in the percentage of university degrees awarded to women. But the
percentage still differs dramatically across fields. Among the Ph.Ds
awarded in 2001, for example, in education 65% of the doctorates
went to women; in the social sciences, 54%; in the life sciences,
47%; in the physical sciences, 26%; in engineering, 17%. This is
completely predictable from the difference in interests between people
and living things, on the one hand, and inanimate objects, on the
other. And the pattern is pretty much the same in 1980 and 2001,
despite the change in absolute numbers. |
||
![]() ![]() |
Third,
risk. Men are by far the more reckless sex. In a large meta-analysis
involving 150 studies and 100,000 participants, in 14 out of 16 categories
of risk-taking, men were over-represented. The two sexes were equally
represented in the other two categories, one of which was smoking, for
obvious reasons. And two of the largest sex differences were in "intellectual
risk taking" and "participation in a risky experiment." We see this sex
difference in everyday life, in particular, in the following category:
the Darwin Awards, "commemorating those individuals who ensure the long-term
survival of our species by removing themselves from the gene pool in
a sublimely idiotic fashion." Virtually all — perhaps all — of
the winners are men. |
||
![]() ![]() |
Fourth,
three-dimensional mental transformations: the ability to determine whether
the drawings in each of these pairs the same 3-dimensional shape. Again
I'll appeal to a meta-analysis, this one containing 286 data sets and
100,000 subjects. The authors conclude, "we have specified a number of
tests that show highly significant sex differences that are stable across
age, at least after puberty, and have not decreased in recent years." Now,
as I mentioned, for some kinds of spatial ability, the advantage goes
to women, but in "mental rotation,"spatial perception," and "spatial
visualization" the advantage goes to men. |
||
![]() ![]() |
Now,
does this have any relevance to scientific achievement? We don't know
for sure, but there's some reason to think that it does. In psychometric
studies, three-dimensional spatial visualization is correlated with mathematical
problem-solving. And mental manipulation of objects in three dimensions
figures prominently in the memoirs and introspections of most creative
physicists and chemists, including Faraday, Maxwell, Tesla, Kéekulé,
and Lawrence, all of whom claim to have hit upon their discoveries by
dynamic visual imagery and only later set them down in equations. A typical
introspection is the following: "The cyclical entities which seem to
serve as elements in my thought are certain signs and more or less clear
images which can be voluntarily reproduced and combined. This combinatory
play seems to be the essential feature in productive thought before there
is any connection with logical construction in words or other kinds of
signs." The quote comes from this fairly well-known physicist. |
||
![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Fifth,
mathematical reasoning. Girls and women get better school grades in mathematics
and pretty much everything else these days. And women are better at mathematical
calculation. But consistently, men score better on mathematical word
problems and on tests of mathematical reasoning, at least statistically.
Again, here is a meta analysis, with 254 data sets and 3 million subjects.
It shows no significant difference in childhood; this is a difference
that emerges around puberty, like many secondary sexual characteristics.
But there are sizable differences in adolescence and adulthood, especially
in high-end samples. Here is an example of the average SAT mathematical
scores, showing a 40-point difference in favor of men that's pretty much
consistent from 1972 to 1997. In the Study of Mathematically Precocious
Youth (in which 7th graders were given the SAT, which of course ordinarily
is administered only to older, college-bound kids), the ratio of those
scoring over 700 is 2.8 to 1 male to female. (Admittedly, and interestingly,
that's down from 25 years ago, when the ratio was 13-to1, and perhaps
we can discuss some of the reasons.) At the 760 cutoff, the ratio nowadays
is 7 males to 1 female. |
||
![]() |
Now
why is there a discrepancy with grades? Do SATs and other tests of mathematical
reasoning aptitude underpredict grades, or do grades overpredict high-end
aptitude? At the Radical Forum Liz was completely explicit in which side
she takes, saying that "the tests are no good," unquote. But if the tests
are really so useless, why does every major graduate program in science
still use them — including the very departments at Harvard and
MIT in which Liz and I have selected our own graduate students? |
||
![]() |
I think the reason is that school grades are affected by homework and by the ability to solve the kinds of problems that have already been presented in lecture and textbooks. Whereas the aptitude tests are designed to test the application of mathematical knowledge to unfamiliar problems. And this, of course, is closer to the way that math is used in actually doing math and science. Indeed,
contrary to Liz, and the popular opinion of many intellectuals, the
tests are surprisingly good. There is an enormous amount of
data on the predictive power of the SAT. For example, people in science
careers overwhelmingly scored in 90th percentile in the SAT or GRE
math test. And the tests predict earnings, occupational choice, doctoral
degrees, the prestige of one's degree, the probability of having
a tenure-track position, and the number of patents. Moreover this
predictive power is the same for men and for women. As for why there
is that underprediction of grades — a slight under-prediction,
one-tenth of a standard deviation — the Educational Testing
Service did a study on that phenomenon, and were able to explain
the mystery by a combination of the choice of major, which differs
between the sexes, and the greater conscientiousness of women. |
||
![]() |
Finally
there's a sex difference in variability. It's crucial here to look at
the right samples. Estimates of variance depend highly on the tails of
the distribution, which by definition contain smaller numbers of people.
Since people at the tails of the distribution in many surveys are likely
to be weeded out for various reasons, it's important to have large representative
samples from national populations. In this regard the gold standard is
the Science paper by Novell and Hedges, which reported six large
stratified probability samples. They found that in 35 out of 37 tests,
including all of the tests in math, space, and science, the male variance
was greater than the female variance. |
||
![]() |
One
other data set meeting the gold standard is displayed in this graph,
showing the entire population of Scotland, who all took an intelligence
test in a single year. The X axis represents IQ, where the mean is 100,
and the Yaxis represents the proportion of men versus women. As you can
see these are extremely orderly data. In the middle part of the range,
females predominate; at both extremes, males slightly predominate. Needless
to say, there is a large percentage of women at both ends of the scale — but
there is also large sex difference. |
||
![]() |
Now
the fact that these six gender differences exist does not mean that they
are innate. This of course is a much more difficult issue to resolve.
A necessary preamble to this discussion is that nature and nurture are
not alternatives; it is possible that the explanation for a given sex
difference involves some of each. The only issue is whether the contribution
of biology is greater than zero. I think that there are ten kinds of
evidence that the contribution of biology is greater than zero,
though of course it is nowhere near 100 percent. |
||
![]() ![]() |
First,
there are many biological mechanisms by which a sex difference could occur.
There are large differences between males and females in levels of sex
hormones, especially prenatally, in the first six months of life, and
in adolescence. There are receptors for hormones all over the brain,
including the cerebral cortex. There are many small differences in men's
and women's brains, including the overall size of the brain (even correcting
for body size), the density of cortical neurons, the degree of cortical
asymmetry, the size of hypothalamic nuclei, and several others. |
||
![]() |
Second, many of the major sex differences — certainly some of them, maybe all of them, are universal. The idea that there are cultures out there somewhere in which everything is the reverse of here turns out to be an academic legend. In his survey of the anthropological literature called Human Universals, the anthropologist Donald Brown points out that in all cultures men and women are seen as having different natures; that there is a greater involvement of women in direct child care; more competitiveness in various measures for men than for women; and a greater spatial range traveled by men compared to by women. In personality,
we have a cross-national survey (if not a true cross-cultural one)
in Feingold's meta-analysis, which noted that gender differences
in personality are consistent across ages, years of data collection,
educational levels, and nations. When it comes to spatial manipulation
and mathematical reasoning, we have fewer relevant data, and we honestly
don't have true cross-cultural surveys, but we do have cross-national
surveys. David Geary and Catherine Desoto found the expected sex
difference in mental rotation in ten European countries and in Ghana,
Turkey, and China. Similarly, Diane Halpern, analyzing results from
ten countries, said that "the majority of the findings show amazing
cross-cultural consistency when comparing males and females on cognitive
tests." |
||
![]() |
Third,
stability over time. Surveys of life interests and personality have shown
little or no change in the two generations that have come of age since
the second wave of feminism. There is also, famously, resistance to
change in communities that, for various ideological reasons, were dedicated
to stamping out sex differences, and found they were unable to do so.
These include the Israeli kibbutz, various American Utopian communes
a century ago, and contemporary androgynous academic couples. |
||
![]() |
In tests of mental rotation, the meta-analysis by Voyer et al found no change over time. In mathematical reasoning there has been a decline in the size of the difference, although it has certainly not disappeared. Fourth,
many sex differences can be seen in other mammals. It would be an
amazing coincidence if these differences just happened to be replicated
in the arbitrary choices made by human cultures at the dawn of time.
There are large differences between males and females in many mammals
in aggression, in investment in offspring, in play aggression play
versus play parenting, and in the range size, which predicts a species'
sex differences in spatial ability (such as in solving mazes), at
least in polygynous species, which is how the human species is classified.
Many primate species even show a sex difference in their interest
in physical objects versus conspecifics, a difference seen their
patterns of juvenile play. Among baby vervet monkeys, the males even
prefer to play with trucks and the females with other kinds of toys! |
||
![]() ![]() |
Fifth, many of these differences emerge in early childhood. It is said that there is a technical term for people who believe that little boys and little girls are born indistinguishable and are molded into their natures by parental socialization. The term is "childless." Some sex differences seem to emerge even in the first week of life. Girls respond more to sounds of distress, and girls make more eye contact than boys. And in a study that I know Liz disputes and that I hope we'll talk about, newborn boys were shown to be more interested in looking at a physical object than a face, whereas newborn girls were shown to be more interested in looking at a face than a physical object. A bit
later in development there are vast and robust differences between
boys and girls, seen all over the world. Boys far more often than
girls engage in rough-and-tumble play, which involves aggression,
physical activity, and competition. Girls spend a lot more often
in cooperative play. Girls engage much more often in play parenting.
And yes, boys the world over turn anything into a vehicle or a weapon,
and girls turn anything into a doll. There are sex differences in
intuitive psychology, that is, how well children can read one another's
minds. For instance, several large studies show that girls are better
than boys in solving the "false belief task," and in interpreting
the mental states of characters in stories. |
||
![]() |
Sixth, genetic boys brought up as girls. In a famous 1970s incident called the John/Joan case, one member of a pair of identical twin boys lost his penis in a botched circumcision (I was relieved to learn that this was not done by a moyl, but by a bumbling surgeon). Following advice from the leading gender expert of the time, the parents agreed to have the boy castrated, given female-specific hormones, and brought up as a girl. All this was hidden from him throughout his childhood. When I was an undergraduate the case was taught to me as proof of how gender roles are socially acquired. But it turned out that the facts had been suppressed. When "Joan" and her family were interviewed years later, it turned out that from the youngest ages he exhibited boy-typical patterns of aggression and rough-and-tumble play, rejected girl-typical activities, and showed a greater interest in things than in people. At age 14, suffering from depression, his father finally told him the truth. He underwent further surgery, married a woman, adopted two children, and got a job in a slaughterhouse. This
is not just a unique instance. In a condition called cloacal exstrophy,
genetic boys are sometimes born without normal male genitalia. When
they are castrated and brought up as girls, in 25 out of 25 documented
instances they have felt that they were boys trapped in girls' bodies,
and showed male-specific patterns of behavior such as rough-and-tumble
play. |
||
![]() |
Seventh, a lack of differential treatment by parents and teachers. These conclusions come as a shock to many people. One comes from Lytton and Romney's meta-analysis of sex-specific socialization involving 172 studies and 28,000 children, in which they looked both at parents' reports and at direct observations of how parents treat their sons and daughters — and found few or no differences among contemporary Americans. In particular, there was no difference in the categories "Encouraging Achievement" and "Encouraging Achievement in Mathematics." There
is a widespread myth that teachers (who of course are disproportionately
female) are dupes who perpetuate gender inequities by failing to
call on girls in class, and who otherwise having low expectations
of girls' performance. In fact Jussim and Eccles, in a study of 100
teachers and 1,800 students, concluded that teachers seemed to be
basing their perceptions of students on those students' actual performances
and motivation. |
||
![]() |
Eighth,
studies of prenatal sex hormones: the mechanism that makes boys boys
and girls girls in the first place. There is evidence, admittedly squishy
in parts, that differences in prenatal hormones make a difference in
later thought and behavior even within a given sex. In the condition
called congenital adrenal hyperplasia, girls in utero are subjected
to an increased dose of androgens, which is neutralized postnatally.
But when they grow up they have male-typical toy preferences — trucks
and guns — compared to other girls, male-typical play patterns,
more competitiveness, less cooperativeness, and male-typical occupational
preferences. However, research on their spatial abilities is inconclusive,
and I cannot honestly say that there are replicable demonstrations
that CAH women have male-typical patterns of spatial cognition. |
||
![]() |
Similarly,
variations in fetal testosterone, studied in various ways, show that
fetal testosterone has a nonmonotic relationship to reduced eye contact
and face perception at 12 months, to reduced vocabulary at 18 months,
to reduced social skills and greater narrowness of interest at 48 months,
and to enhanced mental rotation abilities in the school-age years. |
||
![]() |
Ninth,
circulating sex hormones. I'm going to go over this slide pretty quickly
because the literature is a bit messy. Though it's possible that all
claims of the effects of hormones on cognition will turn out to be bogus,
I suspect something will be salvaged from this somewhat contradictory
literature. There are, in any case, many studies showing that testosterone
levels in the low-normal male range are associated with better abilities
in spatial manipulation. And in a variety of studies in which estrogens
are compared or manipulated, there is evidence, admittedly disputed,
for statistical changes in the strengths and weaknesses in women's cognition
during the menstrual cycle, possibly a counterpart to the changes in
men's abilities during their daily and seasonal cycles of testosterone. |
||
![]() |
My
last kind of evidence: imprinted X chromosomes. In the past fifteen years
an entirely separate genetic system capable of implementing sex differences
has been discovered. In the phenomenon called genetic imprinting, studied
by David Haig and others, a chromosome such as the X chromosome can be
altered depending on whether it was passed on from one's mother or from
one's father. This makes a difference in the condition called Turner
syndrome, in which a child has just one X chromosome, but can get it
either from her mother or her father. When she inherits an X that is
specific to girls, on average she has a better vocabulary and better
social skills, and is better at reading emotions, at reading body language,
and at reading faces. |
||
![]() |
A remark on stereotypes, and then I'll finish. Are these
stereotypes? Yes, many of them are (although, I must add, not all
of them — for example, women's superiority in spatial memory
and mathematical calculation. There seems to be a widespread assumption
that if a sex difference conforms to a stereotype, the difference
must have been caused by the stereotype, via differential
expectations for boys and for girls. But of course the causal arrow
could go in either direction: stereotypes might reflect differences
rather than cause them. In fact there's an enormous literature in
cognitive psychology which says that people can be good intuitive
statisticians when forming categories and that their prototypes for
conceptual categories track the statistics of the natural world pretty
well. For example, there is a stereotype that basketball players
are taller on average than jockeys. But that does not mean that basketball
players grow tall, and jockeys shrink, because we expect them to
have certain heights! Likewise, Alice Eagly and Jussim and Eccles
have shown that most of people's gender stereotypes are in fact pretty
accurate. Indeed the error people make is in the direction of underpredicting
sex differences. |
||
![]() |
To
sum up: I think there is more than "a shred of evidence" for sex differences
that are relevant to statistical gender disparities in elite hard science
departments. There are reliable average difference in life priorities,
in an interest in people versus things, in risk-seeking, in spatial transformations,
in mathematical reasoning, and in variability in these traits. And there
are ten kinds of evidence that these differences are not completely explained
by socialization and bias, although they surely are in part. |
||
![]() |
A concluding remark. None of this provides grounds for ignoring the biases and barriers that do keep women out of science, as long as we keep in mind the distinction between fairness on the one hand and sameness on the other. And I will give the final word to Gloria Steinem: "there are very few jobs that actually require a penis or a vagina, and all the other jobs should be open to both sexes." |
![]() |
(ELIZABETH
SPELKE:) Thanks, especially to Steve; I'm really
glad we're able to have this debate, I've been looking forward
to it. |
||
![]() |
I want to start by talking about the points of agreement between Steve and me, and as he suggested, there are many. If we got away from the topic of sex and science, we'd be hard pressed to find issues that we disagree on. Here are a few of the points of agreement that are particularly relevant to the discussions of the last few months. First, we agree that both our society in general and our university in particular will be healthiest if all opinions can be put on the table and debated on their merits. We also agree that claims concerning sex differences are empirical, they should be evaluated by evidence, and we'll all be happier and live longer if we can undertake that evaluation as dispassionately and rationally as possible. We agree that the mind is not a blank slate; in fact one of the deepest things that Steve and I agree on is that there is such a thing as human nature, and it is a fascinating and exhilarating experience to study it. And finally, I think we agree that the role of scientists in society is rather modest. Scientists find things out. The much more difficult questions of how to use that information, live our lives, and structure our societies are not questions that science can answer. Those are questions that everybody must consider. So where
do we disagree? |
||
![]() |
We disagree on the answer to the question, why in the world are women scarce as hens' teeth on Harvard's mathematics faculty and other similar institutions? In the current debate, two classes of factors have been said to account for this difference. In one class are social forces, including overt and covert discrimination and social influences that lead men and women to develop different skills and different priorities. In the other class are genetic differences that predispose men and women to have different capacities and to want different things. In his book, The Blank Slate, and again today, Steve argued that social forces are over-rated as causes of gender differences. Intrinsic differences in aptitude are a larger factor, and intrinsic differences in motives are the biggest factor of all. Most of the examples that Steve gave concerned what he takes to be biologically based differences in motives. My own view is different. I think the big forces causing this gap are social factors. There are no differences in overall intrinsic aptitude for science and mathematics between women and men. Notice that I am not saying the genders are indistinguishable, that men and women are alike in every way, or even that men and women have identical cognitive profiles. I'm saying that when you add up all the things that men are good at, and all the things that women are good at, there is no overall advantage for men that would put them at the top of the fields of math and science. On the issue of motives, I think we're not in a position to know whether the different things that men and women often say they want stem only from social forces, or in part from intrinsic sex differences. I don't think we can know that now. I want
to start with the issue that's clearly the biggest source of debate
between Steve and me: the issue of differences in intrinsic aptitude.
This is the only issue that my own work and professional knowledge
bear on. Then I will turn to the social forces, as a lay person as
it were, because I think they are exerting the biggest effects. Finally,
I'll consider the question of intrinsic motives, which I hope we'll
come back to in our discussion. |
||
![]() |
Over
the last months, we've heard three arguments that men have greater cognitive
aptitude for science. The first argument is that from birth, boys are
interested in objects and mechanics, and girls are interested in people
and emotions. The predisposition to figure out the mechanics of the world
sets boys on a path that makes them more likely to become scientists
or mathematicians. The second argument assumes, as Galileo told us, that
science is conducted in the language of mathematics. On the second claim,
males are intrinsically better at mathematical reasoning, including spatial
reasoning. The third argument is that men show greater variability than
women, and as a result there are more men at the extreme upper end of
the ability distribution from which scientists and mathematicians are
drawn. Let me take these claims one by one. |
||
![]() |
The first claim, as Steve said, is gaining new currency from the work of Simon Baron-Cohen. It's an old idea, presented with some new language. Baron-Cohen says that males are innately predisposed to learn about objects and mechanical relationships, and this sets them on a path to becoming what he calls "systematizers." Females, on the other hand, are innately predisposed to learn about people and their emotions, and this puts them on a path to becoming "empathizers." Since systematizing is at the heart of math and science, boys are more apt to develop the knowledge and skills that lead to math and science. To anyone as old as I am who has been following the literature on sex differences, this may seem like a surprising claim. The classic reference on the nature and development of sex differences is a book by Eleanor Maccoby and Carol Jacklin that came out in the 1970s. They reviewed evidence for all sorts of sex differences, across large numbers of studies, but they also concluded that certain ideas about differences between the genders were myths. At the top of their list of myths was the idea that males are primarily interested in objects and females are primarily interested in people. They reviewed an enormous literature, in which babies were presented with objects and people to see if they were more interested in one than the other. They concluded that there were no sex differences in these interests. Nevertheless,
this conclusion was made in the early 70s. At that time, we didn't
know much about babies' understanding of objects and people, or how
their understanding grows. Since Baron-Cohen's claims concern differential
predispositions to learn about different kinds of things, you could
argue that the claims hadn't been tested in Maccoby and Jacklin's
time. What does research now show? |
||
![]() |
Let me take you on a whirlwind tour of 30 years of research in one powerpoint slide. From birth, babies perceive objects. They know where one object ends and the next one begins. They can't see objects as well as we can, but as they grow their object perception becomes richer and more differentiated. Babies also start with rudimentary abilities to represent that an object continues to exist when it's out of view, and they hold onto those representations longer, and over more complicated kinds of changes, as they grow. Babies make basic inferences about object motion: inferences like, the force with which an object is hit determines the speed with which it moves. These inferences undergo regular developmental changes over the infancy period. In each
of these cases, there is systematic developmental change, and there's
variability. Because of this variability, we can compare the abilities
of male infants to females. Do we see sex differences? The research
gives a clear answer to this question: We don't. |
||
![]() |
Male and female infants are equally interested in objects. Male and female infants make the same inferences about object motion, at the same time in development. They learn the same things about object mechanics at the same time. Across large numbers of studies, occasionally a study will favor one sex over the other. For example, girls learn that the force with which something is hit influences the distance it moves a month earlier than boys do. But these differences are small and scattered. For the most part, we see high convergence across the sexes. Common paths of learning continue through the preschool years, as kids start manipulating objects to see if they can get a rectangular block into a circular hole. If you look at the rates at which boys and girls figure these things out, you don't find any differences. We see equal developmental paths. I think
this research supports an important conclusion. In discussions of
sex differences, we need to ask what's common across the two sexes.
One thing that's common is infants don't divide up the labor of understanding
the world, with males focusing on mechanics and females focusing
on emotions. Male and female infants are both interested in objects
and in people, and they learn about both. The conclusions that Maccoby
and Jacklin drew in the early 1970s are well supported by research
since that time. |
||
![]() |
Let
me turn to the second claim. People may have equal abilities to develop
intuitive understanding of the physical world, but formal math and science
don't build on these intuitions. Scientists use mathematics to come up
with new characterizations of the world and new principles to explain
its functioning. Maybe males have an edge in scientific reasoning because
of their greater talent for mathematics. |
||
![]() |
As
Steve said, formal mathematics is not something we have evolved to
do; it's a recent accomplishment. Animals don't do formal math or science,
and neither did humans back in the Pleistocene. If there is a biological
basis for our mathematical reasoning abilities, it must depend on systems
that evolved for other purposes, but that we've been able to harness
for the new purpose of representing and manipulating numbers and geometry. |
||
![]() |
Research from the intersecting fields of cognitive neuroscience, neuropsychology, cognitive psychology, and cognitive development provide evidence for five "core systems" at the foundations of mathematical reasoning. The first is a system for representing small exact numbers of objects — the difference between one, two, and three. This system emerges in human infants at about five months of age, and it continues to be present in adults. The second is a system for discriminating large, approximate numerical magnitudes — the difference between a set of about ten things and a set of about 20 things. That system also emerges early in infancy, at four or five months, and continues to be present and functional in adults. The third system is probably the first uniquely human foundation for numerical abilities: the system of natural number concepts that we construct as children when we learn verbal counting. That construction takes place between about the ages of two and a half and four years. The last two systems are first seen in children when they navigate. One system represents the geometry of the surrounding layout. The other system represents landmark objects. All five
systems have been studied quite extensively in large numbers of male
and female infants. We can ask, are there sex differences in the
development of any of these systems at the foundations of mathematical
thinking? Again, the answer is no. I will show you data from just
two cases. |
||
![]() |
The
first is the development of natural number concepts, constructed by children
between the ages of two and four. At any particular time in this period,
you'll find a lot of variability. For example, between the ages of three
and three and a half years, some children have only figured out the meaning
of the word "one" and can only distinguish the symbolic concept one from
all other numbers. Other kids have figured out the meanings of all the
words in the count list up to "ten" or more, and they can use all of
them in a meaningful way. Most kids are somewhere in between: they have
figured out the first two symbols, or the first three, and so forth.
When you compare children's performance by sex, you see no hint of a
superiority of males in constructing natural number concepts. |
||
![]() |
The
other example comes from studies that I think are the closest thing in
preschool children to the mental rotation tests conducted with adults.
In these studies, children are brought into a room of a given shape,
something is hidden in a corner, and then their eyes are closed and they're
spun around. They have to remember the shape of the room, open their
eyes, and figure out how to rotate themselves back to the object where
it was hidden. If you test a group of 4 year olds, you find they can
do this task well above chance but not perfectly; there's a range of
performance. When you break that performance down by gender, again there
is not a hint of an advantage for boys over girls. |
||
![]() |
These
findings and others support two important points. First, indeed there
is a biological foundation to mathematical and scientific reasoning.
We are endowed with core knowledge systems that emerge prior to any
formal instruction and that serve as a basis for mathematical thinking.
Second, these systems develop equally in males and females. Ten years
ago, the evolutionary psychologist and sex difference researcher, David
Geary, reviewed the literature that was available at that time. He
concluded that there were no sex differences in "primary abilities" underlying
mathematics. What we've learned in the last ten years continues to
support that conclusion. |
||
![]() |
Sex differences do emerge at older ages. Because they emerge later in childhood, it's hard to tease apart their biological and social sources. But before we attempt that task, let's ask what the differences are. I think the following is a fair statement, both of the cognitive differences that Steve described and of others. When people are presented with a complex task that can be solved through multiple different strategies, males and females sometimes differ in the strategy that they prefer. For example, if a task can only be solved by representing the geometry of the layout, we do not see a difference between men and women. But if the task can be accomplished either by representing geometry or by representing individual landmarks, girls tend to rely on the landmarks, and boys on the geometry. To take another example, when you compare the shapes of two objects of different orientations, there are two different strategies you can use. You can attempt a holistic rotation of one of the objects into registration with the other, or you can do point-by-point featural comparisons of the two objects. Men are more likely to do the first; women are more likely to do the second. Finally,
the mathematical word problems on the SAT-M very often allow multiple
solutions. Both item analyses and studies of high school students
engaged in the act of solving such problems suggest that when students
have the choice of solving a problem by plugging in a formula or
by doing Ven diagram-like spatial reasoning, girls tend to do the
first and boys tend to do the second. |
||
![]() |
Because of these differences, males and females sometimes show differing cognitive profiles on timed tests. When you have to solve problems fast, some strategies will be faster than others. Thus, females perform better at some verbal, mathematical and spatial tasks, and males perform better at other verbal, mathematical, and spatial tasks. This pattern of differing profiles is not well captured by the generalization, often bandied about in the popular press, that women are "verbal" and men are "spatial." There doesn't seem to be any more evidence for that than there was for the idea that women are people-oriented and men are object-oriented. Rather the differences are more subtle. Does
one of these two profiles foster better learning of math than the
other? In particular, is the male profile better suited to high-level
mathematical reasoning? |
||
![]() |
At this point, we face a question that's been much discussed in the literature on mathematics education and mathematical testing. The question is, by what yardstick can we decide whether men or women are better at math? Some people suggest that we look at performance on the SAT-M, the quantitative portion of the Scholastic Assessment Test. But this suggestion raises a problem of circularity. The SAT test is composed of many different types of items. Some of those items are solved better by females. Some are solved better by males. The people who make the test have to decide, how many items of each type to include? Depending on how they answer that question, they can create a test that makes women look like better mathematicians, or a test that makes men look like better mathematicians. What's the right solution? Books are devoted to this question, with much debate, but there seems to be a consensus on one point: The only way to come up with a test that's fair is to develop an independent understanding of what mathematical aptitude is and how it's distributed between men and women. But in that case, we can't use performance on the SAT to give us that understanding. We've got to get that understanding in some other way. So how are we going to get it? A second strategy is to look at job outcomes. Maybe the people who are better at mathematics are those who pursue more mathematically intensive careers. But this strategy raises two problems. First, which mathematically intensive jobs should we choose? If we choose engineering, we will conclude that men are better at math because more men become engineers. If we choose accounting, we will think that women are better at math because more women become accountants: 57% of current accountants are women. So which job are we going to pick, to decide who has more mathematical talent? These two examples suggest a deeper problem with job outcomes as a measure of mathematical talent. Surely you've got to be good at math to land a mathematically intensive job, but talent in mathematics is only one of the factors influencing career choice. It can't be our gold standard for mathematical ability. So what can be? I suggest the following experiment. We should take a large number of male students and a large number of female students who have equal educational backgrounds, and present them with the kinds of tasks that real mathematicians face. We should give them new mathematical material that they have not yet mastered, and allow them to learn it over an extended period of time: the kind of time scale that real mathematicians work on. We should ask, how well do the students master this material? The good news is, this experiment is done all the time. It's called high school and college. Here's the outcome. In high school, girls and boys now take equally many math classes, including the most advanced ones, and girls get better grades. In college, women earn almost half of the bachelor's degrees in mathematics, and men and women get equal grades. Here I respectfully disagree with one thing that Steve said: men and women get equal grades, even when you only compare people within a single institution and a single math class. Equating for classes, men and women get equal grades. The outcome
of this large-scale experiment gives us every reason to conclude
that men and women have equal talent for mathematics. Here, I too
would like to quote Diane Halpern. Halpern reviews much evidence
for sex differences, but she concludes, "differences are not deficiencies." Men
and women have equal aptitude for mathematics. Yes, there are sex
differences, but they don't add up to an overall advantage for one
sex over the other. |
||
Let
me turn to the third claim, that men show greater variability, either
in general or in quantitative abilities in particular, and so there
are more men at the upper end of the ability distribution. I can go
quickly here, because Steve has already talked about the work of Camilla
Benbow and Julian Stanley, focusing on mathematically precocious youth
who are screened at the age of 13, put in intensive accelerated programs,
and then followed up to see what they achieve in mathematics and other
fields. |
|||
![]() |
Fortunately, Benbow, Stanley and Lubinski have collected much more data on these mathematically talented boys and girls: not just the ones with top scores on one timed test, but rather the larger sample of girls and boys who were accelerated and followed over time. Let's look at some of the key things that they found. First,
they looked at college performance by the talented sample. They found
that the males and females took equally demanding math classes and
majored in math in equal numbers. More girls majored in biology and
more boys in physics and engineering, but equal numbers of girls
and boys majored in math. And they got equal grades. The SAT-M not
only under-predicts the performance of college women in general,
it also under-predicted the college performance of women in the talented
sample. These women and men have been shown to be equally talented
by the most meaningful measure we have: their ability to assimilate
new, challenging material in demanding mathematics classes at top-flight
institutions. By that measure, the study does not find any difference
between highly talented girls and boys. |
||
![]() ![]() |
So,
what's causing the gender imbalance on faculties of math and science?
Not differences in intrinsic aptitude. Let's turn to the social factors
that I think are much more important. Because I'm venturing outside
my own area of work, and because time is short, I won't review all
of the social factors producing differential success of men and women.
I will talk about just one effect: how gender stereotypes influence
the ways in which males and females are perceived. Some studies have interviewed parents just after the birth of their child, at the point where the first question that 80% of parents ask — is it a boy or a girl? — has been answered. Parents of boys describe their babies as stronger, heartier, and bigger than parents of girls. The investigators also looked at the babies' medical records and asked whether there really were differences between the boys and girls in weight, strength, or coordination. The boys and girls were indistinguishable in these respects, but the parents' descriptions were different. At 12 months of age, girls and boys show equal abilities to walk, crawl, or clamber. But before one study, Karen Adolph, an investigator of infants' locomotor development, asked parents to predict how well their child would do on a set of crawling tasks: Would the child be able to crawl down a sloping ramp? Parents of sons were more confident that their child would make it down the ramp than parents of daughters. When Adolph tested the infants on the ramp, there was no difference whatever between the sons and daughters, but there was a difference in the parents' predictions. My third example, moving up in age, comes from the studies of Jackie Eccles. She asked parents of boys and girls in sixth grade, how talented do you think your child is in mathematics? Parents of sons were more likely to judge that their sons had talent than parents of daughters. A panoply of objective measures, including math grades in school, performance on standardized tests, teachers' evaluations, and children's expressed interest in math, revealed no differences between the girls and boys. Still, there was a difference in parents' perception of their child's intangible talent. Other studies have shown a similar effect for science. There's
clearly a mismatch between what parents perceive in their kids and
what objective measures reveal. But is it possible that the parents
are seeing something that the objective measures are missing? Maybe
the boy getting B's in his math class really is a mathematical genius,
and his mom or dad has sensed that. To eliminate that possibility,
we need to present observers with the very same baby, or child, or
Ph.D. candidate, and manipulate their belief about the person's gender.
Then we can ask whether their belief influences their perception. |
||
![]() |
It's hard to do these studies, but there are examples, and I will describe a few of them. A bunch of studies take the following form: you show a group of parents, or college undergraduates, video-clips of babies that they don't know personally. For half of them you give the baby a male name, and for the other half you give the baby a female name. (Male and female babies don't look very different.) The observers watch the baby and then are asked a series of questions: What is the baby doing? What is the baby feeling? How would you rate the baby on a dimension like strong-to-weak, or more intelligent to less intelligent? There are two important findings. First, when babies do something unambiguous, reports are not affected by the baby's gender. If the baby clearly smiles, everybody says the baby is smiling or happy. Perception of children is not pure hallucination. Second, children often do things that are ambiguous, and parents face questions whose answers aren't easily readable off their child's overt behavior. In those cases, you see some interesting gender labeling effects. For example, in one study a child on a video-clip was playing with a jack-in-the-box. It suddenly popped up, and the child was startled and jumped backward. When people were asked, what's the child feeling, those who were given a female label said, "she's afraid." But the ones given a male label said, "he's angry." Same child, same reaction, different interpretation. In other
studies, children with male names were more likely to be rated as
strong, intelligent, and active; those with female names were more
likely to be rated as little, soft, and so forth. |
||
![]() |
I
think these perceptions matter. You, as a parent, may be completely committed
to treating your male and female children equally. But no sane parents
would treat a fearful child the same way they treat an angry child. If
knowledge of a child's gender affects adults' perception of that child,
then male and female children are going to elicit different reactions
from the world, different patterns of encouragement. These perceptions
matter, even in parents who are committed to treating sons and daughters
alike. |
||
![]() |
I will give you one last version of a gender-labeling study. This one hits particularly close to home. The subjects in the study were people like Steve and me: professors of psychology, who were sent some vitas to evaluate as applicants for a tenure track position. Two different vitas were used in the study. One was a vita of a walk-on-water candidate, best candidate you've ever seen, you would die to have this person on your faculty. The other vita was a middling, average vita among successful candidates. For half the professors, the name on the vita was male, for the other half the name was female. People were asked a series of questions: What do you think about this candidate's research productivity? What do you think about his or her teaching experience? And finally, Would you hire this candidate at your university? For the walk-on-water candidate, there was no effect of gender labeling on these judgments. I think this finding supports Steve's view that we're dealing with little overt discrimination at universities. It's not as if professors see a female name on a vita and think, I don't want her. When the vita's great, everybody says great, let's hire. What about the average successful vita, though: that is to say, the kind of vita that professors most often must evaluate? In that case, there were differences. The male was rated as having higher research productivity. These psychologists, Steve's and my colleagues, looked at the same number of publications and thought, "good productivity" when the name was male, and "less good productivity" when the name was female. Same thing for teaching experience. The very same list of courses was seen as good teaching experience when the name was male, and less good teaching experience when the name was female. In answer to the question would they hire the candidate, 70% said yes for the male, 45% for the female. If the decision were made by majority rule, the male would get hired and the female would not. A couple
other interesting things came out of this study. The effects were
every bit as strong among the female respondents as among the male
respondents. Men are not the culprits here. There were effects at
the tenure level as well. At the tenure level, professors evaluated
a very strong candidate, and almost everyone said this looked like
a good case for tenure. But people were invited to express their
reservations, and they came up with some very reasonable doubts.
For example, "This person looks very strong, but before I agree to
give her tenure I would need to know, was this her own work or the
work of her adviser?" Now that's a perfectly reasonable question
to ask. But what ought to give us pause is that those kinds of reservations
were expressed four times more often when the name was female
than when the name was male. |
||
![]() |
So there's a pervasive difference in perceptions, and I think the difference matters. Scientists' perception of the quality of a candidate will influence the likelihood that the candidate will get a fellowship, a job, resources, or a promotion. A pattern of biased evaluation therefore will occur even in people who are absolutely committed to gender equity. I have
little doubt that all my colleagues here at Harvard are committed
to the principle that a male candidate and a female candidate of
equal qualifications should have equal chance at a job. But we also
think that when we compare a more productive scholar to a less productive
one, a more experienced teacher to a less experienced one, a more
independent investigator to a less independent one, those factors
matter as well. These studies say that knowledge of a person's gender
will influence our assessment of those factors, and that's going
to produce a pattern of discrimination, even in people with the best
intentions. |
||
![]() |
From the moment of birth to the moment of tenure, throughout this great developmental progression, there are unintentional but pervasive and important differences in the ways that males and females are perceived and evaluated. I have to emphasize that perceptions are not everything. When cases are unambiguous, you don't see these effects. What's more, cognitive development is robust: boys and girls show equal capacities and achievements in educational settings, including in science and mathematics, despite the very different ways in which boys and girls are perceived and evaluated. I think it's really great news that males and females develop along common paths and gain common sets of abilities. The equal performance of males and females, despite their unequal treatment, strongly suggests that mathematical and scientific reasoning has a biological foundation, and this foundation is shared by males and females. Finally,
you do not create someone who feels like a girl or boy simply by
perceiving them as male or female. That's the lesson that comes from
the studies of people of one sex who are raised as the opposite sex.
Biological sex differences are real and important. Sex is not a cultural
construction that's imposed on people. |
||
![]() |
But the question on the table is not, Are there biological sex differences? The question is, Why are there fewer women mathematicians and scientists? The patterns of bias that I described provide four interconnected answers to that question. First, and most obviously, biased perceptions produce discrimination: When a group of equally qualified men and women are evaluated for jobs, more of the men will get those jobs if they are perceived to be more qualified. Second, if people are rational, more men than women will put themselves forward into the academic competition, because men will see that they've got a better chance for success. Academic jobs will be more attractive to men because they face better odds, will get more resources, and so forth. Third,
biased perceptions earlier in life may well deter some female students
from even attempting a career in science or mathematics. If your
parents feel that you don't have as much natural talent as someone
else whose objective abilities are no better than yours, that may
discourage you, as Eccles's work shows. Finally, there's likely to
be a snowball effect. All of us have an easier time imagining ourselves
in careers where there are other people like us. If the first three
effects perpetuate a situation where there are few female scientists
and mathematicians, young girls will be less likely to see math and
science as a possible life. |
||
![]() |
So by my personal scorecard, these are the major factors. Let me end, though, by asking, could Steve also be partly right? Could biological differences in motives — motivational patterns that evolved in the Pleistocene but that apply to us today — propel more men than women towards careers in mathematics and science? My feeling
is that where we stand now, we cannot evaluate this claim. It may
be true, but as long as the forces of discrimination and biased perceptions
affect people so pervasively, we'll never know. I think the only
way we can find out is to do one more experiment. We should allow
all of the evidence that men and women have equal cognitive capacity,
to permeate through society. We should allow people to evaluate children
in relation to their actual capacities, rather than one's sense of
what their capacities ought to be, given their gender. Then we can
see, as those boys and girls grow up, whether different inner voices
pull them in different directions. I don't know what the findings
of that experiment will be. But I do hope that some future generation
of children gets to find out. |
PINKER: Thanks, Liz, for a very stimulating and apposite presentation. A number of comments. I don't dispute a lot of the points you made, but many have lost sight of the datum that we're here to explain in the first place. Basic abilities like knowing that an object is still there when you put a hankie over it, or knowing that one object can't pass through another, are not the kinds of things that distinguish someone who's capable of being a professor of physics or math from someone who isn't. And in many of the cases in which you correctly said that there is no gender difference in kids, there is no gender difference in adults either — such as the give-a-number task and other core abilities. Also, a big concern with all of the null effects that you mentioned is statistical power. Bob Rosenthal 20 years ago pointed out that the vast majority of studies that psychologists do are incapable of detecting the kinds of results they seek, which is why it's so important to have meta-analyses and large sample sizes. I question whether all of the null results that you mentioned can really be justified, and whether they are comparable to the studies done on older kids and adults. One place where I really do disagree with you is in the value of the SAT-M, where the "circle" has amply been broken. This is what people at the College Board are obsessed with. What you are treating as the gold standard is performance in college courses. But the datum we are disputing is not how well boys and girls do in school, or how well men and women do in college, because there we agree there is no male advantage. The phenomenon we really are discussing is performance at the upper levels: getting tenure-track job, getting patents, and so on. And here the analyses have shown that the SAT is not biased against girls. That is, a given increment in SAT score predicts a given increment in the variable of interest to the same extent whether you're male or female. I think there may be a slight difference in which finding each of us is alluding to in talking about differences in grades. I was not suggesting that girls' better grades come about because they take easier courses; they really do get better grades holding courses constant. Rather it's the slight underprediction of grades by the SAT that can be explained in part by class choice and in part by conscientiousness. SPELKE: Well the most recent thing that I've read about this issue is the Gallagher and Kaufman book, Gender Differences in Mathematics, which just came out about a month ago. They report that equating for classes and institutions, and looking just at A students, there's a 21 point SAT math differential; that is to say, for two students getting the same grade of A, the average for the girls on the SAT will have been 21 points lower. That differential is there at every grade level and in all the courses. The SAT people have discussed it as a problem. One of the discussions reached the conclusion that the SAT is still useful, because although it under-predicts girls' performance in college, girls' grades over-predict their performance in college, and if you use the two together you are okay. In fact, they advised that people never take account of the SAT simply by itself, but consider it in relation to grades. When you spoke earlier about the use of GREs in admitting people to grad school, that's in fact what graduate programs do: We consider both grades and GREs. Interestingly, though, in all of the public discussion of the relative advantages of men versus women for math and science, over the last two months, people have not used the SAT in conjunction with grades. When talking about relative ability, they've used the SAT by itself. I think that has led to a distorted conversation about this issue. PINKER: It nonetheless remains true that in the most recent study by Lubinski and Benbow, which showed a fantastic degree of predictive power of the SAT given in 7th grade, there was no difference in predictive power in boys and girls in any of these measures. But let me return to the datum that is at issue here, namely the differential representation of the sexes in physical sciences, mechanical engineering, and mathematics. The fact that men and women are equal overall in spatial abilities, and overall in mathematical abilities, is irrelevant to this. It may be that the particular subtalents in which women excel make them more likely to go into accounting. But the datum we are discussing is not a gender difference in accounting. The datum we are discussing is a gender difference in the physical sciences, engineering, and mathematics. And I suspect that when you look at a range of professions, the size of the sex discrepancy correlates with how much spatial manipulation (not just any kind of spatial cognition) and how much mathematical reasoning (not just any kind of mathematical ability) each of those jobs requires. What about parents' expectations? In the 1970s the model for development was, "as the twig is bent, so grows the branch." — that subtle differences in parents' perceptions early in life can have a lasting effect. You nudge the child in a particular direction and you'll see an effect on his trajectory years later. But there is now an enormous amount of research spearheaded by the behavioral genetics revolution suggesting that that is not true. There may be effects of parental expectations and parental treatment on young children while they're still in the home, but most follow-up studies show that short of outright abuse and neglect, these effects peter out by late adolescence. And studies of adoption and of twins and other sibs reared apart suggest that any effects of the kinds of parenting that are specific to a child simply reflect the preexisting genetic traits of the child, and the additional effect of parenting peters out to nothing. SPELKE: Can I respond to that? I think one thing is different about the gender case, compared to the early socialization effects for other kinds of categories, different styles of parenting, and so forth. The gender differences that we see reflected in parents' differing perceptions are mirrored by differing perceptions that males and females experience throughout their lives. It's not the case that idiosyncratic pairs of parents treat their kids one way, but then as soon as the children leave that environment, other people treat them differently. Rather, what we have in the case of gender is a pervasive pattern that just keeps getting perpetuated in different people. I'm rather a nativist about cognition, and I am tempted to look at that pattern and wonder, did Darwin give us some innately wrong idea about the genders? Professionals in professional contexts show the same patterns of evaluation that parents show in home contexts, and children face those patterns of evaluation, not just when they're young and at home, but continuing through high school, college, and finally with their colleagues on academic faculties. We're dealing here with a much more pervasive effect than the effects of socialization in the other studies that you've written and talked about. PINKER: Regarding bias: as I mentioned at the outset, I don't doubt that bias exists. But the idea that the bias started out from some arbitrary coin flip at the dawn of time and that gender differences have been perpetuated ever since by the existence of that bias is extremely unlikely. In so many cases, as Eagly and the Stereotype-Accuracy people point out, the biases are accurate. Also, there's an irony in these discussion of bias. When we test people in the cognitive psychology lab, and we don't call these base rates "gender," we applaud people when they apply them. If people apply the statistics of a group to an individual case, we call it rational Bayesian reasoning, and congratulate ourselves for getting them to overcome the cognitive illusion of base rate neglect. But when people do the same thing in the case of gender, we treat Bayesian reasoning as a cognitive flaw and base-rate neglect as rational! Now I agree that applying base rates for gender in evaluating individual men and women is a moral flaw; I don't think that base rates ought to be applied in judging individuals in most cases of public decision-making. But the fact that the statistics of a gender are applied does not mean that their origin was arbitrary; it could be statistically sound in some cases. SPELKE: Let me reply to that, because I agree that the origin is not arbitrary, and that the bias is there for an objective reason, but I think you're drawing the wrong conclusion about it. I think the reason there's a bias to think that men have greater natural talent for math and science is that when we look around the world and ask, who's winning the Nobel Prizes and making the great advances in science, what we see, again and again, is men. Although Linda Buck received this year's Nobel Prize in physiology or medicine, for the most part it's overwhelmingly men who are reaching the upper levels of math and science. It's natural to look at that and think, there must be some reason, some inner difference between men and women, which produces this enormous disparity. And I quite agree with you that good statistical reasoning should lead you to think, the next student who comes along, if male, is more likely to join that group of Nobel Prize winners. What I would like to suggest is that we have good reasons to resist this kind of conclusion, and the reasons aren't only moral. Let me just use an analogy, and replay this debate over the biological bases of mathematics and science talent 150 years ago. Let's consider who the 19th century mathematicians and scientists were. They were overwhelmingly male, just as they are today, but also overwhelmingly European, not Asian. You won't see a Chinese face or an Indian face in 19th century science. It would have been tempting to apply this same pattern of statistical reasoning and say, there must be something about European genes that give rise to greater mathematical talent than Asian genes do. If we go back still further, and play this debate in the Renaissance, I think we would be tempted to conclude that Catholic genes make for better science than Jewish genes, because all those Renaissance scientists were Catholic. If you look at those cases, you see what's wrong with this argument. What's wrong with the argument is not that biology is irrelevant. If Galileo had been switched at birth with some baby from the Pisan ghetto, the baby raised by Galileo's parents would not likely have ended up teaching us that the language of physics is mathematics. I think that Galileo's genes had something to do with his achievement, but so did Galileo's cultural and social environment: his nurturing. Genius requires huge amounts of both. If, in that baby switch, Galileo had found himself growing up in the Pisan ghetto, I bet he wouldn't have ended up being the example in this discussion today either. So yes, there are reasons for this statistical bias. But I think we want to step back and ask, why is it that almost all Nobel Prize winners are men today? The answer to that question may be the same reason why all the great scientists in Florence were Christian. PINKER:
I think you could take the same phenomenon and come to the opposite
conclusion! Say there were really was such a self-reinforcing, self-perpetuating
dynamic: a difference originates for reasons that might be arbitrary;
people perceive the difference; they perpetuate it by their expectations.
Just as bad, you say, is the fact that people don't go into fields
in which they don't find enough people like themselves. If so, the
dynamic you would expect is that the representation of different genders
or ethnic groups should migrate to the extremes. That is, there is
a positive feedback loop where if you're in the minority, it will discourage
people like you from entering the field, which will mean that there'll
be even fewer people in the field, and so on. On either side of this
threshold you should get a drift of the percentages in opposite directions. SPELKE: I'm glad you brought up the case of the basketball and baseball players. I think it's interesting to ask, what distinguishes these cases, where you remove the overt discrimination and within a very short period of time the differential disappears, from other cases, where you remove the overt discrimination and the covert discrimination continues? In the athletic cases where discrimination disappears quickly, there are clear, objective measures of success. Whatever people think about the capacities of a black player, if he is hitting the ball out of the park, he is going to get credit for a home run. That is not the case in science. In science, the judgments are subjective, every step of the way. Who's really talented? Who deserves bigger lab space? Who should get the next fellowship? Who should get promoted to tenure? These decisions are not based on clear and objective criteria. These are the cases where you see discrimination persisting. You see it in academia. You see it in Claudia Goldin's studies of orchestra auditions, which also involve subtle judgments: Who's the more emotive, sensitive player? If you know that the players are male or female, you're going pick mostly men, but if the players are behind a screen, you'll start picking more women. PINKER: But that makes the wrong prediction: the harder the science, the greater the participation of women! We find exactly the opposite: it's the most subjective fields within academia — the social sciences, the humanities, the helping professions — that have the greatest representation of women. This follows exactly from the choices that women express in what gives them satisfaction in life. But it goes in the opposite direction to the prediction you made about the role of objective criteria in bringing about gender equity. Surely it's physics, and not, say, sociology, that has the more objective criteria for success. SPELKE: Let me just say one thing, because I didn't say much in the talk at all, about this issue of motives, and biological differences in motives. That's been a less controversial issue, but I think it's an important one, and most of your examples were concerned with it. I think it's a really interesting possibility that the forces that were active in our evolutionary past have led men and women to evolve somewhat differing concerns. But to jump from that possibility into the present, and draw conclusions about what people's motives will be for pursuing one or another career, is way too big a stretch. As we both agree, the kinds of careers people pursue now, the kinds of choices they make, are radically different from anything that anybody faced back in the Pleistocene. It is anything but clear how motives that evolved then translate into a modern context. Let me just give one example of this. You've suggested, as a hypothesis, that because of sexual selection and also parental investment issues, men are selected to be more competitive, and women are selected to be more nurturant. Suppose that hypothesis is true. If we want to use it to make predictions about desires for careers in math and science, we're going to have to answer a question that I think is wide open right now. What makes for better motives in a scientist? What kind of motives are more likely to lead to good science: Competitive motives, like the motive J. D. Watson described in The Double Helix, to get the structure of DNA before Linus Pauling did? Or nurturant motives of the kind that Doug Melton has described recently to explain why he's going into stem cell research: to find a cure for juvenile diabetes, which his children suffer from? I think it's anything but clear how motives from our past translate into modern contexts. We would need to do the experiment, getting rid of discrimination and social pressures, in order to find out.
|
![]() |
John Brockman The son of a Boston wholesale flower seller, he adapted his father's business methods in his work as a pop publicist and management consultant. He went on to become a successful literary agent, specialising in top science writers and — with an online 'intellectual salon' — building a reputation as a tireless promoter of influential ideas. Interview by Andrew Brown The
Anyone
today who thinks that scientists are the unacknowledged legislators
of the world has been influenced by Brockman's taste. As
well as Dawkins, he represents Daniel Dennett, Jared Diamond,
and Sir Martin Rees, as well as three Nobel prize winners
and almost all the other famous popular scientists. His old
friend Stewart Brand, the publisher of the Whole Earth
Catalog and later the promoter of the Clock of the Long
Now, which is intended to run for 10,000 years, says: "It's
so easy to think the guy's just a high-class pimp that it's
quite easy to ignore the impact on the intellectual culture
of the west that John has enabled by getting his artist and
scientist friends out to the world. There is a whole cohort
of intellectuals who are interacting with each other and
would not [be able to] without John." He even mentions Huey P Newton, the Black Panther. "Sometime around 1987 or '88, I get a call from Huey, who was a close friend of mine, who I was trying to avoid, because it had been revealed that he was actually gratuitously murdering people . . . you know, shooting them. He was flipping out. He wasn't talking about revolution or anything. Newton's message said: 'Me and my buddy Bob Trivers — we're going to write a book on deceit and self-deception.'" Robert Trivers was one of the most important evolutionary biologists of the past 50 years, and came up with the hugely influential idea of "reciprocal altruism" as a graduate student at Harvard in the early 70s before his career was interrupted by psychological problems and he went off to live in the Jamaican jungle for some years. (He is now back at Harvard, in a chair funded by a friend of Brockman's.) Brockman continues: "Soon after that, he [Newton] died a very nasty death: just a crummy sidewalk dope deal. This was no way for a real revolutionary . . . "A
couple of years ago, I made a rare visit to LA and was doing
my favourite thing: watching the movie stars round the pool,
and I got a message: Bob Trivers called. 'John. It's Bob
Trivers. As I was saying. I've got the proposal ready. It's
for a book on deceit and self-deception.'" Such a book will
be ideal Brockman fodder. It takes science out to the edges
of society yet deals with subjects of eternal importance.
It captures a theory at the stage when it is most vigorously
fighting for its life. It is written by the man who made
the discovery, which is an important point. Many would agree that at least half his clients are truly remarkable thinkers, but there is room for disagreement about which half. For instance, he represents Sir John Maddox, the former editor of Nature, but also Rupert Sheldrake, whose heretical ideas about biology were denounced by Maddox in a Nature editorial that suggested Sheldrake's book A New Science of Life be burnt. Brockman has sold most of Richard Dawkins' books, but also the Bible Code by Michael Drosnin, which claimed that everything significant in the world up to the death of Princess Diana could have been predicted by reading every seventh letter in the Hebrew Bible, and the novel The Diary of a Manhattan Call Girl by Tracy Quan, which was the first account of a prostitute's life to be serialised on the Internet. "He
likes proposals to be about two pages long, no more, and
then he likes to get an auction going," one of his authors
says. "You'll get a call from him, and he's walking down
Fifth Avenue on his cellphone, saying that he's got Simon & Schuster
to bid 100,000 and now he will see what happens. A quarter
of an hour later, Bantam has bid 125,000 and then he says
he'll go back to S&S and see if he can get 150,000. But he's
got an attention span of about half an hour. If the book
isn't sold within a week, forget it." This is how the young Brockman learned from his father, a broker in the wholesale flower market in Boston, to hustle sales. "He dominated the carnation industry. He would go to the Boston flower market, which was owned by the growers, who formed a cooperative. All these Swedes and Norwegians would be growing gladiolas and carnations and they'd bring them in at three in the morning and leave them like a long aisle. There'd be thousands of flowers, and you had to sell them, or they died. He said to me 'you gotta move them, they're going to die'. And one day, 40 years later, I'm on the phone, and I had a chilling feeling as I felt my father's voice coming through me, like, 'they're going to die'. So, why am I always so fixated on closing the deal, getting the next book in? It comes from that experience. That was a pure market situation. So, that's the way I run my business. It's not literary. It's not publishing. It's business. I have got properties to sell, on behalf of my clients. "My job is to do the best I can for them and I do it by making a market. The market decides. But knowing how to make a market involves . . . some capacities." The capacities are at the heart of his business, but it's hard to describe them. He has a keen sense for interesting ideas, but also for the ways in which they fit into society. For instance, he would never call himself an atheist, he says, in America: "I mean I don't believe: I'm sure there's no God. I'm sure there's no afterlife. But don't call me an atheist. It's like a losers' club. When I hear the word atheist, I think of some crummy motel where they're having a function and these people have nowhere else to go. That's what it means in America. In the UK it's very different." The Brockmans were the children of immigrants — John's father's family had come from Austria — and grew up in a largely poor and Catholic neighbourhood of Boston and he remains extremely sensitive to anti-Semitism. "There were no books in our house. My father could barely read. He was a brilliant man but he was on the streets working at eight years old. My mother read a little bit, but, you know, it was a little encyclopedia. "My parents were poor. My father started a business the day I was born which became a successful business. But we grew up in a tough neighbourhood called Dorchester, which was an Irish-Catholic bastion, where this radical right-wing priest went up and down the streets telling people to kill Jews. So that's how my brother and I grew up." He has one brother, a retired physicist, who is three years older. "We quickly found out, going to school, that . . . we were personally responsible for the death of Jesus Christ. We had a lot of fighting to do, and most of it on the losing end, because there were always 30 of them to two of us. My brother got the worse of it. My mother was a tough cookie. She would kick him out of the house if he didn't fight hard enough. Luckily in those days you didn't get killed; you just got a bloody nose. But it was tough." "Confusion is good. Then try awkwardness. Then you fall back on contradiction. Those are my three friends." This
mixture of pugnacity and sensitivity about ethnicity can
still surface. When he was upset by a profile in the Sunday
Times magazine, which he thought played to an anti-Semitic
stereotype, he complained straight to Rupert Murdoch (using
Murdoch's banker, another of his contacts, as an intermediary). In
this flux, it seemed the only certainty was scientific truth,
but he was early attracted to the idea of science, of computing
as a metaphor for everything. Stewart Brand first met him
in the early 60s: "I was in the army as an officer and spending
the weekends in New York — he was in the thick of the
multimedia scene that was the cutting edge of performance
pop art. He was an impresario, who could help organise events
and people and media and be essential to the process, but
unlike a lot of people he was actually alert to what the
art was about, just as later, as an agent, he was alert to
what the books were about. So far as I was concerned he was
another artist in the group of artists I was running with."
In 1967 Brockman discovered how to sell flower power while it was still fresh. A business school friend who had gone to work for a paper company asked Brockman to help motivate the sales force for their line of sanitary towels. This was at a time when the New York Times was solemnly explaining that "Total environment" discothèques, such as Cheetah and The Electric Circus in New York, were turning on their patrons with high-decibel rock'n'roll combined with pulsing lights, flashing slide images, and electronic "colour mists". Brockman asked — and got — a fee of $15,000 despite having no consulting experience. He put on a multimedia show for the salesmen: they lay on the floor of a shiny vinyl wigwam while four sound systems played them Beatles songs, bird calls, company advertising slogans with an executive shouting about market statistics and competitive products, and a film showed a young woman wearing a dress made of the company's paper which she ripped down to her navel. In the 60s it was cutting-edge art, an "intermedia kinetic experience", and the salesmen exposed to it reportedly sold an additional 17% of feminine hygiene products in the next quarter. Brockman took the show around nine cities for the company, energising its sales force nationwide, and was established as a consultant who could sell his services to anyone. But
it was not enough. His book By the Late John Brockman was
unfavourably reviewed, but he was not discouraged and continued
to write and edit books — 18 at last count. One, Einstein,
Gertrude Stein, Wittgenstein and Frankenstein , had
to be hurriedly withdrawn after portions were found to have
been plagiarised from an article by James Gleick, the author
of Chaos , one of the first big pop science hits and not
a Brockman client. Brockman blamed one of his assistants. Brockman has constantly reinvented himself. He has been at the leading edge of intellectual fashion for the past 30 years. In the late 90s, just before the dot.com bubble popped, he told an interviewer from Wired magazine that he wanted to be "post-interesting". Looking back on all the ideas he has enthused about you glimpse a mind that rushes around like a border collie — tirelessly and gracefully pursuing anything that moves, but absolutely uninterested in things that stay still, and liable, if shut up in a car, to get bored and eat all the upholstery. Like a lot of successful salesmen, part of his secret is that he is interested in people for their own sake as well as for what they can do for him, and can study them with extraordinary concentration, solemnly placing out, beside the journalist's machine, two tape recorders of his own at the beginning of an interview. To be under his attentive, almost affectionate gaze, is to know how a sheep feels in front of a collie. Twice
in the course of a couple of hours' chat he says "you ought
to write a book about that". He became a book agent by accident.
He was talking about God to the scientist John Lilly, a friend
of Brand's, whose research into dolphins and LSD was one
of the first tendrils of a scientific study of consciousness,
and he realised Lilly had a book there. He sold the proposal
and found a new business where his talents and his interests
coincided. "Throughout history, only a small number of people have done the serious thinking for everybody" He works with and is married to Katinka Matson, the daughter of a New York literary agent who was AD Peters's partner in 50s. "She actually makes the wheels turn in the office," says Tom Standage. The Brockmans have one son, Max, who works in the family business as a third-generation agent, and who was blessed in his crib by a drunken dance performed round it by Hunter S Thompson, Dennis Hopper and Gerd Stern, a multi-media artist from the avant-garde scene. After
the first boom in personal computers and their software blew
out, Brockman was perfectly placed for the next boom, in
writing about the people who made it. The house magazine
of that boom was Wired, which sold itself to Conde Nast as "The
magazine which branded the digital age"; it is almost an
obligation on the editor of Wired to be a Brockman client.
He set out his manifesto in the early 90s for what he called
the Third Culture: "Traditional American intellectuals are,
in a sense, increasingly reactionary, and quite often proudly
(and perversely) ignorant of many of the truly significant
intellectual accomplishments of our time. Their culture,
which dismisses science, is often non-empirical. By contrast,
the Third Culture consists of those scientists and other
thinkers in the empirical world who, through their work and
expository writing, are taking the place of the traditional
intellectual in rendering visible the deeper meanings of
our lives, redefining who and what we are." For
Brockman, America now is the intellectual seedbed for Europe
and Asia. He wrote: "The emergence of the Third Culture introduces
new modes of intellectual discourse and reaffirms the pre-eminence
of America in the realm of important ideas. Throughout history,
intellectual life has been marked by the fact that only a
small number of people have done the serious thinking for
everybody else. What we are witnessing is a passing of the
torch from one group of thinkers, the traditional literary
intellectuals, to a new group, the intellectuals of the emerging
Third Culture. Intellectuals are not just people who know
things but people who shape the thoughts of their generation.
An intellectual is a synthesiser, a publicist, a communicator." Brockman,
it hardly needs saying, is the true intellectual's agent. Yet it is a tribute to Brockman's personality that people who have known him a long time like him a great deal. Stewart Brand says: "The salon-keeper has an interesting balancing act between highlighting the people they're attracted to and also having a strong enough personality so that they are taken seriously as a peer. People do not feel threatened by him or competitive with him. They either admire him or profess to be amused by him. But you look behind that, and you realise that they don't look down on him at all." The magic circle has gone by different names and using different degrees of formality. In the 90s it was a manifested in a physical gathering, run with Heinz Pagels, called the Reality Club. The elite would come together and talk about the work that interested them. They didn't have to be his clients, and many of them weren't. But all invested their time in ideas he was promoting. Pagels died in an accident and Brockman says he didn't have the heart to go on by himself. Instead, he set up his Edge website, where he puts up new interviews every month, which can be read as transcripts or watched as videos, with commentaries. It
all reinforces his idea that reality is essentially social.
Even the name, the Reality Club, goes right back to his earliest
big idea: that reality is what the smart people, who should
be friends of John Brockman, decide to make of the world: "It's
an argument that I have with all my scientist friends, and
I lose it every time. They don't buy it at all. It's very
primitivistic, I'm told, or even solipsism, but it works
for me."
|
Linda S. Gottfredson responds to Simon Baron-Cohen |
LINDA
S. GOTTFREDSON Researchers
in vocational interest
measurement, personality
assessment, personnel
testing, and differential
psychology have spent
a century parsing,
cataloguing, and
correlating these
differences among
individuals. They
find a regular pattern
of sex differences
regardless of age,
time, or place. It
is not clear where
Baron-Cohen's systematizer-empathizer
distinction fits
in this much-explored
territory, but it
would seem to map
best onto dimensions
in the non-cognitive
realm: sympathetic
vs. cold ("agreeableness" personality
dimension), "realistic" vs. "social" vocational
interests, or valuing "ideas" vs. "feeling." |
EDGE BOOKS |
All
new essays by 27 leading Edge contributors..."Good,
narrative history, combined with much fine
writing...quirky, absorbing and persuasive
in just the way that good stories are."—Nature "Some
of the biggest brains in the world turn
their lenses on their own lives...fascinating...an
invigorating debate."—Washington
Post "Compelling."—Discover " An
engrossing treat of a book...crammed with
hugely enjoyable anecdotes ...you'll have
a wonderful time reading these reminiscences."—New
Scientist "An intriguing
collection of essays detailing the childhood
experiences of prominent scientists and
the life events that sparked their hunger
for knowledge. Full of comical and thought-provoking
stories."—Globe & Mail "An
inspiring collection of 27 essays by leading
scientists about the childhood moments
that set them on their shining paths."—Psychology
Today |
The best of Edge, now available in a book..."Provocative and fascinating." — La Stampa "A stellar cast of thinkers tackles the really big questions facing scientists." — The Guardian "A compact, if bumpy, tour through the minds of some of the world's preeminent players in science and technology." — Philadelphia Inquirer "What a show they put on!"— San Jose Mercury News "a very important contribution, sparkling and polychromatic."—Corriere della Sera Published in the UK as Science at the Edge (Weidenfeld) |
Original essays by 25 of the world's leading scientists..."Entertaining" —New Scientist "Provocative" —Daily Telegraph "Inspired"—Wired "Mind-stretching" —Times Higher Education Supplement "Fascinating"—Dallas Morning News "Dazzling" —Washington Post Book World |
John Brockman, Editor and Publisher |
|Top| |